College 5 Flashcards

1
Q

What is a descriptive theory about?

A

How do people make decisions?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

What is a normative theory about?

A

How should people make decisions?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Economists’ perspective: How much is a certain outcome worth?

A
  • Desirability of outcome.
  • Likelihood of obtaining outcome.
  • If low on one, it loses worth.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Three principles of outcome value

A
  • Principle of diminishing sensitivity.
  • Relativity principle.
  • Principle of loss aversion.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

What is the principle of diminishing sensitivity?

A
  • As value increases, the perceived increase of value decreases.
  • Also known as ‘diminishing marginal returns’.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

What is the relativity principle?

A

Evaluation is relative to a neutral reference point.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

What is the principle of loss aversion?

A
  • Losses loom larger than gains.
  • We attach more value to the things we already own.
  • … Because we do not want to lose what we already have, especially after longer ownership and physical possession.
    o The endowment effect.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

What is the expected value theory?

A

Economists’ perspective: how should people make decisions under uncertainty?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

What does the expected value theory argue?

A

They argue that people are

  • Rational
  • Self-centered
    o In every decision that we make, we only think about our own interest.
  • Stable in their preferences
    o No matter the context, we always go for the same option because that is what we value to a certain extend.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

St. Petersburg Paradox

A

Imagine the following gamble

  • A fair coin is tossed….
    o If heads appears you win 2 euros and the game continues.
    o If heads appears again, you win 4 euros and the game continues.
    o If heads appears again, you win 8 euros and the game continues.
    o Etc.
    o The first time tails appears, the game ends.
  • How much should people be willing to pay as a buy in?
    o Expected value: (1/2 x 2) + (1/4 x 4) + (1/8 x 8) + … = 1 + 1 + 1 + … = an infinite amount of money
    o Yet almost no human being is willing to do that
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Bernoulli’s solution

A

“The determination of the value of an item must not be based on the price, but rather on the utility it yields. […] There is no doubt that a gain of one thousand ducats is more significant to the pauper than to a rich man though both gain the same amount.”

  • Money has different “utility” (psychological value) based on various things, e.g., how much of it you already have.

When you’re in the desert, the first bottle of water is amazing. The second bottle, not so much.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Diminishing marginal returns

A

The more (money) one has, the less worth it has.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

What was found in a study on cab drivers on diminishing marginal returns?

A

It is found that cab drivers, on a rainy day, often stop working in the afternoon because they have earned enough on that day. While logic would say they could better continue working, so that they can have a day off on a sunny day or have a buffer.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

What does diminishing marginal returns have implications for?

A

Achievement & motivation

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

What is diminishing marginal returns also known as?

A

Principle of diminishing sensitivity

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

The infamous indifference map

A

Two features with the same utility

  • E.g., income and leisure
  • Should be interchangeable
  • Both have diminishing marginal utility
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

Bernoulli’s error in the indifference map

A

Reference point is missing.

How much income and leisure do you already have?

18
Q

Endowment effect

A

We attach more value to the thing we already own.

19
Q

What did the article by Nash & Rosenthal (2014) show?

A

They manipulated the reference point and showed the endowment effect.

20
Q

What did the experiment by Nash & Rosenthal (2014) look like?

A

Two students can give their top three choices for a residence hall. One student gets her top choice (A), the other doesn’t (B).

The student that got her first choice is asked how much money she would be willing to accept to move to residence hall B The other student is asked how much money she would be willing to pay to get a spot in residence hall A.

They asked the same question after they had lived in their residence hall for two months.

21
Q

What are the results from the experiment by Nash & Rosenthal (2014)?

A

The student that was awarded her first choice rated the value 5.5 at first, and later at 6.2. The student that was denied her first choice rated the value of residence hall A as 2.5 at first and later as 2.2.

There is a big difference between how much you would be willing to pay or to accept. The student that has something to lose, values their residence hall much more than students that have something to gain.

The student that did not get their first choice, has started to grow towards their residence hall.

22
Q

What are the results from Nash & Rosenthal (2014) contrary to?

A

The results are contrary to expected value and expected utility because based on expected utility preference for the residence hall should have the exact same value or utility for both students.

23
Q

How is the relativity principle linked to the experiment with the residence halls?

A
  • Evaluation is relative to a neutral reference point.
  • Forfeiture vs. acquisition choice
    o Forfeiture: losing something
    o Acquisition: something to gain
  • In the case of the student and their residence halls, the neutral reference point is the residence hall that they have vs. what they want.
24
Q

Imagine you can gamble by tossing a coin. With heads you win X euros, with tails you lose 10 euros. How high must X be for you to accept this bet? And if you repeat the bet 100 times?

A

A loss feels twice as much as a win might feel. A lot of people are asking for a lot of money for this bet.

But if you repeat this bet 100 times with X higher than 10, you are guaranteed to make money, considering it’s a 50% chance every time.

25
Q

The principle of loss aversion

A

Same principle of diminishing marginal returns applies also to losses.

But losses loom LARGER than gains (negativity bias).

And there is a neutral reference point.

26
Q

What principle or theory does the following belong to? “If you have already lost 10.000 euros, the extra 1.000 euros doesn’t hurt as much to lose.”

A

The principle of loss aversion

27
Q

When placing bets, when do we prefer the safe option and when the risky option? And how can this be explained by theory?

Bet 1:

  • Option A = 100% chance to win 500 euros
  • Option B = 50% chance to win 1000 euros

Bet 2:

  • Option A = 100 % chance to win 5 euros
  • Option B = 0,1% chance to win 5000 euros

Bet 3:

  • Option A = 100% chance to lose 500 euros
  • Option B = 50% chance to lose 1000 euros

Bet 4:

  • Option A = 100% chance to lose 5 euros
  • Option B = 0,1% chance to lose 5000 euros
A

Most people choose the safer option A in Bet 1 but the riskier option B in Bet 2.

This flips when we’re talking about losses. In Bet 3 most people choose the riskier option B and in Bet 4 most people choose the safer option A.

Both wins and both losses have the same expected values. But the utility of 1000 euros is relatively low compared to 500 euros (diminishing marginal returns). Which explains loss aversion.

28
Q

How do people make medical decisions under uncertainty? And how can this be explained?

Outbreak of unknown Asian Disease.
If you do nothing, 600 people are expected to die.

Do you choose treatment A or B?

Treatment A: saves 200 lives.
Treatment B: probability of 1/3 that all 600 lives will be saved and probability of 2/3 that no lives will be saved.

Do you choose treatment C or D?

Treatment C: 400 people die.
Treatment D: probability of 1/3 that no one will die and probability of 2/3 that 600 people will die.

A

Treatment A: saves 200 lives (72% chose this option).
Treatment B: probability of 1/3 that all 600 lives will be saved and probability of 2/3 that no lives will be saved (28% chose this option).

Treatment C: 400 people die (22% chose this option).
Treatment D: probability of 1/3 that no one will die and probability of 2/3 that 600 people will die (78% chose this option).

But: treatments A and C are exactly the same, as well as treatments B and D. Why the sudden change? –> loss aversion.

29
Q

Political decisions under uncertainty

A

When in uncertainty people choose the riskier option. They choose expected utility over expected performance.

E.g., Trump was chosen over Clinton even though Clinton was a safer option.

30
Q

What tactic is used in the following: Mattresses with 100 night trial, you already have it, you don’t want to lose it.

A

The endowment effect

31
Q

What tactic is used in the following: Netflix showing you what you miss out on if you stop your subscription.

A

Loss aversion

32
Q

People have difficulty interpreting very low and very high chances. What are the implications of this?

A

Very low chances are overestimated

  • For gains people become risk seeking (lotteries).
    o 0.1% to win 5.000 euros
  • For losses, people become risk averse (insurances).
    o 0.1% to lose 5.000 euros
33
Q

When do people become risk averse?

A

When there is fear of disappointment or fear of large loss people accept an unfavorable settlement.

E.g., cashing out with stocks or paying insurance.

34
Q

When do people become risk seeking?

A

When they have hope to avoid loss or hope of a large gain people reject a favorable settlement.

E.g., taking part in lotteries or gambling.

35
Q

What is the experiment by Wohl et al. (2014) on economic threat?

A

Newspaper article: Global financial crisis will soon hit students. The current financial crisis would result in additional tuition fees and greater difficulty securing loans. An investment in higher education may not even be enough to secure the few positions available in this unstable economic climate.

Control condition: newspaper article on money production at the Royal Canadian Mint.

Subjects received 10 dollars for participation.

Opportunity to participate in a study on gambling.

36
Q

What were the results of the experiment by Wohl et al. (2014) on economic threat?

A

Under economic threat, more people chose to gamble!

48% vs. 23% in the control condition.

“No threat vs. economic threat” has an effect on “Amount wagered”
This effect is moderated by “Perceived need to engage in financial risk-taking”

When traditional moneymaking routes are not available, alternate routes (e.g., gambling) need to be considered.

37
Q

What can you say about the following statement: “People try to maximize their outcomes.”

A

It depends.

When it concerns gains, only to a certain point (e.g., taxi drivers).

We do want to avoid losses.

38
Q

What can you say about the following statement: “People attach less value to new things than to things they already have.”

A

Yes

39
Q

What can you say about the following statement: “People are more risk averse when their economic prospects look grim.”

A

No

40
Q

What can you say about the following statement: “People are consistent in their preferences.”

A

No/ it depends (both are correct).

Your preferences flip around based on:

  • Low vs. high probabilities
  • Wins vs. losses