Exam Style Q Flashcards
(46 cards)
rule of law overall structure
IntroSedley’s quote → why question imp → defintion → upholds uncodified principles → importance → thesis1FoundationalCRA 2005 s.1 and s.17 → Jackson 2005 obiter dicta → R(unison) 2017 tribunal fee 2need for evolutionoudated → 3 pillars → critics(jennings, cheney v conn, hra 1998)3evolving - Aliveraz-procedural → bingham-substantive → proscons → rich powerful guiding principal4Practicedlegality, accountability, limiting power → entick v carrington(seizing) → ex parte Pierson [1997] (legal clarity) → unison 2017(access)5Critiqueddiff interpration(att gen 2023)→ undeterminate(sedley) → judicial discrecial overreach → neglected by PS anyway(millelr no.2) → balanceConclusionthesis → practice over theory due to uncodified → rol strongest today → broader contex
Rule of Law Intro
Introduction Lord Justice Sedley: “Everyone believes in the rule of law, but no one agrees what it means.” Definition - The rule of law, although inherently cotested, broadly caters to the principle of justice- that the government must act lawfully, and individuals are entitled to legal protection and fair treatment. This principle, affirmed in cases like UNISON and theorised by Lord Bingham, underpins the UK’s uncodified constitution by ensuring legality, fairness, and accountability. Importance - This principle is particularly vital in the context of the United Kingdom’s uncodified constitution, where the absence of a single written document elevates the rule of law as a fundamental mechanism for constraining government power, upholding accountability, and safeguarding individual rights. Thesis - Although the rule of law is abstract and debated in scope, it plays a fundamental role in guiding UK constitutional law by limiting state power, protecting rights, and supporting judicial oversight, particularly in the absence of codified constraints.
rule of law as foundational
- Foundational Status in UK Law TS: The foundational nature, reflected both in judicial dicta and in statutory recognition. Jackson [2005] made bold obiter dicta describing the rule of law as “the ultimate controlling factor on which our constitution is based,” highlighting its position as a core principle in the absence of a codified constitution. Similarly, in R (UNISON) [2017], reaffirmed that the executive cannot use delegated legislation to undermine fundamental rights like access to the courts. These judicial statements underscore the rule of law’s role as a practical check on executive authority. Its importance is further entrenched by statute: Section 1 of the Constitutional Reform Act 2005 expressly states that “nothing in this Part adversely affects the existing constitutional principle of the rule of law,” while Section 17 places a duty upon the Lord Chancellor to respect and uphold it. conclusion: not merely a political ideal but an active constitutional standard enforced by both courts and institutions of government.
A.V. Dicey’s classical rule of law
- Evolved from A.V. Dicey’s Classic View The rule of law’s foundational status is uncontested, but its capacity to function as a guiding principle today depends on recognising the limitations of Dicey’s formulation and embracing more expansive, modern interpretations. Outdated, classical, and ambiguous viewpoint his three pillars: legality, equality, common law that individuals should only be punished in accordance with the law (legality), that all persons are equal before the law (equality), and that individual rights are best protected through judicial decisions rather than codified texts. (common law) too inattentive to rights and administration equality and legality shot down - too idealisitic and too narrow to be a reliable guiding principle without moral content. - As Jennings observed, Dicey ignored the reality that equality before the law is often illusory in practice. there can always be oppressive laws common law shot down - These ideas were reflected in cases like Cheney v Conn [1968], where the court upheld the primacy of statute codification hate short down - his dismissal of written constitutions and human rights protections makes his conception less useful in a system now shaped by instruments like the Human Rights Act 1998. Although Dicey’s doctrine introduces core values, its lack of engagement with modern legal developments undermines its ability to offer sufficiently certain or comprehensive guidance in contemporary constitutional adjudication. While Dicey’s formulation captured the spirit of the 19th-century constitutional order, its narrow formalism fails to accommodate the complexities of modern governance, rights-based adjudication, and executive discretion rendering it an inadequate framework for understanding the role the rule of law plays in contemporary UK public law.
Raz v Bingham on Rule of Law
- Has had debate Competing Conceptions (Raz vs Bingham) showcases importance, alive, felxibility Raz adopts a formal conception, which views the rule of law as a purely procedural ideal — concerned with the qualities of laws themselves rather than their content. For Raz, a legal system upholds the rule of law if its laws are clear, public, prospective, stable, and applied by an independent judiciary. prioritises legality, certainty, predictability, and institutional order criticised for immorality, tolerating unjust or oppressive laws, so long as they are properly enacted. In contrast, Lord Bingham advances a substantive conception of the rule of law, arguing that it must also include respect for fundamental rights, access to justice, equality before the law, and adherence to international obligations reflects the evolving expectations of a modern constitutional democracy — Sir Jeffrey Jowell, argue that this version better reflects the practical and normative role the rule of law plays in safeguarding human dignity and limiting state power. Contrast strengths & weaknesses (e.g. formal = clear, but tolerates bad laws) judicial overreach - too much power and no praliamentary sovereignty; also less precise - By including values like equality and rights, courts might interpret law based on moral or political ideals. The tension between these two schools of thought reflects the broader debate over whether the rule of law should remain a neutral procedural standard or evolve into a more value-laden, rights-oriented constitutional doctrine. This debate underscores why the rule of law remains conceptually contested — yet also why it remains such a rich and powerful guiding principle in constitutional practice.
Rule of Law Interpretation, Practice, Accountability
- Rule of Law defines Judicial Practice and Government Accountability While the theoretical divergence between Raz and Bingham reveals the conceptual richness of the rule of law, its continued constitutional relevance is most clearly demonstrated through its practical application by the courts, particularly in the domains of statutory interpretation and judicial review. Beyond theory, the rule of law plays a central role in judicial interpretation and statutory application through the principle of legality — the idea that public bodies, including the government, may not interfere with fundamental rights without clear legal authority. This principle was famously affirmed in Entick v Carrington, where the court held that executive agents had no lawful authority to enter and seize property without statutory basis. Lord Camden’s judgment established a foundational limit on executive power: “If it is law, it will be found in our books. If it is not to be found there, it is not law.” In R v Secretary of State for the Home Department, ex parte Pierson [1997], the House of Lords affirmed that Parliament is not presumed to legislate contrary to fundamental rights unless it does so in express terms. This judicial stance reinforces the rule of law by compelling legal clarity when core liberties are at stake. Furthermore, the rule of law underpins interpretive duties under the Human Rights Act 1998. This positions the judiciary as an active guardian of legality, ensuring that public power is exercised within lawful limits and with respect for fundamental rights. Perhaps the most striking example of the rule of law in practice is the Supreme Court’s decision in R (UNISON) v Lord Chancellor [2017]. There, the Court struck down employment tribunal fees on the basis that they unlawfully restricted access to justice, a core component of the rule of law. Lord Reed emphasised that laws which prevent individuals from enforcing their rights are themselves inconsistent with the rule of law. Through the principle of legality and interpretive restraint, it is illustrated that the the rule of law is not merely an abstract ideal but a living principle, operationalised through judicial review to ensure that government action remains legally accountable and rights-respecting.
crtiques for the rule of law
ambiguity Despite its widespread acceptance, the rule of law has been repeatedly criticised for its conceptual vagueness and variable application. Diff interprtation Even the Attorney General (2023) acknowledged the ongoing tension between narrow procedural and broad substantive definitions, each carrying different implications for constitutional interpretation. no one knows which - As Lord Justice Sedley aptly observed, “Everyone believes in the rule of law, but no one agrees what it means.” This ambiguity has led some scholars and practitioners to question whether the doctrine is too indeterminate to serve as a reliable legal standard. invites judicial discretion, allowing courts to impose contested moral values under the guise of constitutional principle - bingham’s principles judicial overreach neglected by parliamentary sovereignty - Miller (No. 2) [2019], although t Prime Minister’s prorogation of Parliament was unlawful, not based on a direct application of the rule of law, but accountability and justiciability . Yet, paradoxically, the very ambiguity that draws criticism also accounts for the rule of law’s enduring relevance. In a legal system without a codified constitution, its flexible, evolving character allows it to adapt to changing democratic values, while still offering a very nuanced, principled framework for limiting state power and playing the role of a modern, dynamic constitution. Far from being a weakness, this dynamic quality may be precisely what gives the rule of law its constitutional strength in a modern, pluralistic democracy.
rule of law conclusion
Conclusion In sum, while the rule of law may be conceptually abstract and the subject of ongoing theoretical debate, its practical enforcement and judicial application ensure that it remains a powerful and functional guiding principle in UK constitutional law. From its foundational role in statutory interpretation and judicial review to its embodiment in landmark decisions such as UNISON, the doctrine continues to shape how power is exercised and constrained within the state. Admittedly, tensions persist — particularly due to the UK’s uncodified constitution and the continued supremacy of Parliament — yet the judiciary’s increasingly active role in upholding legality, fairness, and rights illustrates the rule of law operating in action rather than in theory alone. In a constitution defined by its adaptability, the rule of law remains its most enduring and essential constant. In an age of rising executive power, political polarisation, and democratic uncertainty, the rule of law remains a vital constitutional compass — ensuring that governance in the UK stays anchored in legality, accountability, and rights, even without the security of a written constitution.
SOP Overall
Intromontesquieu definition purpose uk problem structure thesis Why formed why partialmontesquieu why barendt why bagehot why not babrber why not hence partial no sop no democracysopdemocracyleg & execClear fusion, but SOP still matters via checks functional accountability. Important for limiting executive dominance within Parliament.personnel overlap controlled by exec executive overreach whips and party majority - no independencehol, pmqs and select committees for checks (these checks prove to be imp)scrutiny mechanisms ensure accountabilityleg & judSOP is formal here, but influence flows both ways. judicial influence supports democratic values through rights protection.quasi legislative role (lord bingham) can read in (Ghaidan v Godin-Mendoza) judges aren’t electedparliamentary sovereignty HOC disqualification act ensures law comply with HRA 1998 legal flexibility exec & jud This is where SOP is most visible and most essential in modern UK — ensures legality, protects rights.AG courts avoid high policy can resist implementation politcial backlashCRA 2005 reformed lord chancellor judicial independence R(Evans) v AG Acts as Check 1. Fire Brigade Union (follow duties) 2. Treasury v Ahmed (executive overreach) 3. R-Anderson v SSHD (unlawful sentencing) futureheading towards greater sop CRA UKSC USA France conclusionIn a time of rising executive dominance and democratic fragility, SOP acts as a constitutional compass—guiding reform, empowering the judiciary, and ensuring governance remains rooted in legality, liberty, and accountability.
SOP intro
🔹 INTRO Definition: SOP = division of power between legislature, executive, and judiciary, so no branch can concentrate unchecked power (Montesquieu, The Spirit of the Laws, 1748). Purpose: Prevent tyranny, uphold liberty, ensure institutional checks and balances. UK context: Uncodified constitution, parliamentary sovereignty → fusion of powers (especially Leg–Exec). Thesis: UK does not reflect a pure SOP model, but the doctrine remains important as a guiding principle in structuring government, limiting overreach, and protecting judicial independence. Structure: 1. Historical foundations → 2–4. Institutional analysis (Leg–Exec, Exec–Judic, Leg–Judic) → 5. Future and comparisons → 6. Conclusion.
why sop
🔹 1. Why SOP Was Created (Historic + Continued Importance) Montesquieu: Saw SOP as essential to liberty; admired what he (wrongly) believed was SOP in English constitution. Barendt: SOP’s role = prevent arbitrary government, ensure legal accountability. Bagehot (1867): Critiqued SOP in UK context — called fusion the UK’s “efficient secret” that ensures political stability. Nick Barber: In UK, SOP is more about efficiency than liberty — total separation would cause deadlock. ✅ Takeaway: UK constitution has never strictly followed SOP, but it continues to serve as a valuable organising principle that safeguards rule of law and limits government overreach.
SOP leg exec
🔹 2. Legislature & Executive: Fusion, But With Checks Where SOP fails: Ministers (PM, Cabinet) drawn from Parliament → personnel overlap. Executive controls parliamentary timetable, whip system, and benefits from majority dominance. This fusion = strong government, but risks executive overreach. Where SOP partially applies: PMQs, select committees, and House of Lords → function as checks, not separation. Where it works for democracy: Accountability through scrutiny mechanisms — reflects a pragmatic SOP adapted to democracy. Where it’s undemocratic: Whips and party discipline mean Parliament often fails to act independently. ✅ Takeaway: Clear fusion, but SOP still matters via functional accountability. Important for limiting executive dominance within Parliament.
sop leg-jud
🔹 3. Legislature & Judiciary: Formal Separation, Functional Overlap Where SOP exists: Parliament is sovereign → courts can’t strike down Acts. House of Commons (Disqualification) Act 1975: disqualifies judges/civil servants from sitting as MPs — creates some institutional separation. Where SOP is blurred: Courts have a quasi-legislative role via interpretation, esp. post-HRA 1998 s.3. 📝 Lord Bingham: Judges do not create law outright but “develop it in the interstices”. Can “read in” or reinterpret laws to align with rights. Ghaidan v Godin-Mendoza [2004] – “Spouse” reinterpreted under HRA to include same-sex couples. Where it’s democratic: Protects minority rights and ensures laws comply with rights obligations. Judicial interpretation increases legal flexibility without overriding Parliament. Where it’s undemocratic: Judges are unelected, but may be seen as shaping policy. ✅ Takeaway: SOP is formal here, but influence flows both ways. Interpretation under the HRA shows how judicial influence supports democratic values through rights protection.
sop jud-exec
🔹 4. Executive & Judiciary: Increasing Separation, Politically Sensitive Where SOP is achieved: Constitutional Reform Act 2005: Created UK Supreme Court (2009) — removed judges from HoL. Reformed Lord Chancellor role (no longer judge + minister + speaker). Strengthened judicial independence. R (Evans) v AG [2015] – SC overturned AG’s veto of Prince Charles’ letters → judicial independence. Where SOP is still weak: Attorney General: remains legal adviser and political actor — tension between independence and influence. Courts avoid “high policy” areas (e.g. GCHQ case on national security). Where it helps democracy: Judiciary acts as a check on executive power (especially via judicial review and HRA 1998). Fire Brigades Union [1995] – Exec must follow statutory duties; can’t ignore law. Treasury v Ahmed [2010] – Executive overreach via Orders in Council ruled unlawful. R (Anderson) v SSHD [2003] – Sentencing by Home Secretary violated Article 6; power moved to judiciary. Enhances rule of law, protects fundamental rights. Where it’s problematic: Executive can still resist implementation of judgments (e.g. political backlash post-Evans case). ✅ Takeaway: This is where SOP is most visible and most essential in modern UK — ensures legality, protects rights.
sop future and conclusion
🔹 5. Future of SOP in the UK: Comparative and Evolutionary Outlook UK model is evolving → flexible, uncodified, but reforms (CRA 2005, UKSC) show trend toward greater separation. Courts now assert greater independence and play a role in checking executive abuse. Comparative systems: USA = rigid SOP with constitutional court and presidential system. France = clear separation, civil law structure, constitutional council. UK = partial SOP, reinforced through judicial review, HRA, institutional reforms. ✅ Takeaway: UK is unlikely to adopt rigid SOP, but judicial developments and comparative standards are pushing it toward more defined and balanced power relationships. 🔹 CONCLUSION The UK constitution does not follow a strict SOP, but the doctrine remains crucially important for maintaining balance and accountability. Leg–Exec relationship shows clear fusion, but scrutiny mechanisms matter. Exec–Judiciary interaction demonstrates how SOP protects legality and rights. Judiciary–Legislature overlap reveals judicial creativity, yet democratically justified via human rights obligations. The UK’s approach is pragmatic, evolving, and responsive—not rigidly separated, but deeply influenced by the spirit of SOP. In a time of rising executive dominance and democratic fragility, SOP acts as a constitutional compass—guiding reform, empowering the judiciary, and ensuring governance remains rooted in legality, liberty, and accountability.
PS overall structure
intro Definition → Contemporary tension due to various factors → evolved into practical sovereignty dicey’s classical PS Core Tenants → Quote EU and PS suboridnation → ECA 1972 s.2(4) supremacy of EU → factortame & Merchant Shipping Act → Lord Bridge → Galrand v British Rail (courts new duty) Judical reform after legal complications on EU withdrawal 2018 → miller 1 miller 2 established parliamentary accountability and judicial oversight → Jackson v AG courts guard RoL Legal pluralism HRA 1998 editing rights → Ghaidan v Godin-Mednoza → Devolution bills dissolved rights → Gender Recognition Bill/Equality Act/Reserved matters still judicial review still sovereign Constitutional Statues Ellen v MOH orthodox → Thoburn distinction and hierarchy → Constitutional Principles and mechanisms Conclusion Practical Sovereignty and Legality → gialogue nunaced model → Lord Justice Laws quote
PS intro - Definition → Contemporary tension due to various factors → evolved into practical sovereignty
💼 INTRODUCTION (Define and Establish Importance) Definition (Dicey’s Classical View): A.V. Dicey defines Parliamentary Sovereignty as the doctrine that Parliament has the right to make or unmake any law whatever and no person or body is recognized by law as having the right to override or set aside the legislation of Parliament. Contemporary Relevance: This doctrine is foundational to the UK’s unwritten constitution and reflects the principle of legislative supremacy. However, it faces increasing tension with modern constitutional developments—e.g., EU membership, devolution, Human Rights Act 1998.
PS Dicey 3 views plus quote
🧱 PART 1 – DICEY’S DOCTRINE (Traditional View) Core Tenets: Legislative Supremacy: Parliament can legislate on any matter. No Entrenchment: Parliament cannot bind future Parliaments. No Judicial Review: No court can challenge an Act’s validity. Key Quote: “The principle of Parliamentary Sovereignty means neither more nor less than this, namely, that Parliament… has… the right to make or unmake any law whatever.” — Dicey
PS under EU -> act section saying no supreme -> Factame Merchant Shipping Act -> Garland v British Rail judges
🇪🇺 PART 2 – EU Membership History 📌 A. EU Membership (Past Impact) practical subordination of sovereignty ECA 1972 s.2(4): Expressed intention to give EU law primacy—statutory hook of EU construction as a mechanism of implied limitation. Factortame [No.2] [1991]: Prime deciding case of UK vs EU. Merchant Shipping Act 1988 was overridden due to conflict with EU law. House of Lords disapplied UK legislation — a first in UK constitutional law. Lord Bridge: This was a consequence accepted by Parliament when it passed ECA 1972. 💬 Legal sovereignty yielded in practice to comply with EU law. ⚠️ Parliamentary sovereignty was qualified by EU law obligations. Judicial Interpretation of Parliamentary Intent during Brexit Courts began using statutory interpretation duty to presume compliance with EU law (e.g., Garland v British Rail). Parliament no longer seen as legislating in isolation—its intent filtered through EU obligations.
Post Brexit PS - legal complications on EU withdrawal 2018 → miller 1 miller 2 established parliamentary accountability and judicial oversight → Jackson v AG courts guard RoL
⚖️ PART 3 – Practical Sovereignty Concept✨Post-Brexit Judicial Independence and Impact on Parliamentary Legal Sovereignty ‘New Orthodoxy’ Legal sovereignty weakened — Parliament could legislate contrary to EU law, but courts would refuse to apply it. Shift from absolute to conditional supremacy. 📌 Post-Brexit Position European Union (Withdrawal) Act 2018 & 2020 ✅ Formal sovereignty restored—but legal complexities (e.g., Northern Ireland Protocol) create new practical constraints. In Miller (No.1) and Miller (No.2), courts actively held the executive accountable to Parliament, reinforcing judicial oversight as part of constitutional order. Miller (No.1) [2017]: Parliament role in authorising the triggering Article 50. Reinforces principle that only Parliament can alter rights under UK law. Miller (No.2)/Cherry [2019]: Prorogation unlawful calls for judicial scrutiny: courts uphold constitutional principles, including Parliamentary accountability. Judicial Recognition of Modified Sovereignty (dialogue model of constitutionalism): Jackson v AG [2005]: Lord Steyn & Lady Hale hint that rule of law might trump Parliamentary sovereignty in extreme cases. “The rule of law enforced by the courts is the ultimate controlling factor.” Lords like Steyn and Hope suggested that courts might refuse to obey even a parliamentary statute if it undermined the rule of law. This hints that courts no longer see their role as passive enforcers of sovereignty—but as guardians of constitutional principles.
HRA 1998 editing rights → Ghaidan v Godin-Mednoza → Devolution bills dissolved rights → Gender Recognition Bill/Equality Act/Reserved matters still judicial review still sovereign
☮️ PART 4 – Legal Pluralism - not only judicial, but HRA, devolution - political and legal limits. There are areas where legal pluralism—multiple sources of authority—coexist, and sovereignty is not the sole kingmaker. 📌 C. Human Rights Act 1998 s.3 & s.4 HRA: Courts are allowed interpret legislation compatibly with ECHR “so far as possible”, but cannot strike it down. A “soft” constraint on sovereignty creating dialogue and a collaborative relationship Example Case: Ghaidan v Godin-Mendoza [2004] — courts stretched meaning of a statute to comply with ECHR rights. 📌 D. Devolution Scotland Act 1998 s.28(8): Expresses intent not to legislate over devolved matters without consent. Convention only, reaffirmed in Miller No.1: not legally binding. A contemporary example of devolved legislative tension is the UK Government’s use of s.35 of the Scotland Act 1998 to block the Gender Recognition Reform (Scotland) Bill 2022, passed by the Scottish Parliament. This was the first-ever use of the power, impact on UK-wide equality law. conflicted with the Equality Act 2010, a reserved matter, thereby justifying intervention. constitutional overreach, triggering a live judicial review illustrating that political consent does not ensure legal finality under a framework where Westminster remains the ultimate legal authority. This case highlights the fragility of devolved autonomy and the enduring supremacy of Parliament despite modern pluralist pressures.
PS contritutional principle - orthodx Ellen v MOH, thoburn disticntion hierarchy -> constitutional principles and mechansims
📜 PART 5 – CONTEMPORARY CONCEPTS: CONSTITUTIONAL PRINCIPLES? Entrenchment Practices but might change: “This Act may not be repealed except by a two-thirds majority” — not enforceable. Ellen Street Estates v Minister of Health - orthodox rule Doctrine: Parliament cannot bind its successors. In Thoburn, DISTINCTIONN Lord Justice Laws distinguished constitutional statutes that can’t be impliedly repealed and required express repeal This creates a hierarchy among Acts of Parliament, which Dicey’s model explicitly rejected. Rise of Constitutional Principles – Rule of law, legality, democracy guide judicial review, checks and balances, parliamentary mechanisms
PS conclusion
✅ CONCLUSION (Evaluative Summary) Dicey’s doctrine retains formal strength, especially post-Brexit, but its practical reality is eroded by external influences (EU law legacy, HRA, devolution) and evolving judicial attitudes. There is now a ‘dialogue’ model of constitutionalism—sovereignty coexists with legality, accountability, and human rights norms. UK’s constitutional structure is shifting from unquestioned supremacy to a qualified, pluralist sovereignty. more practical Parliamentary sovereignty is] a construct of the common law”—Lord Justice Laws, Thoburn
HRA overall
Intro hr → hra → hra evolution → bogdanor quote → thesis s.3 key qualities → application in r v a, ghaidan v godin mendoza, re s → quasi leg/judicial creativity s.4 key qualities → belinger → nicklinson v justice → softer, constitutional dialogue → followed by legislative action Pros - RoL, SOP, 3 pillars RoL(Bingham, UNISON) → SoP(Miller 1, collaborative constitutionalism) → legal, fair accountability (s.6) Cons - Democracy Sovereignty Democracy v unelected → s.3/2 biased → constrained/no power acc → majoritarian abuse prevent → Jackson quote ECHR s.2 → domestic optional application → R(Ullah) applied → R v Horncastle didn’t apply Bill of Rights proposal → changes → pros → cons Conclusion new constitutional sovereignty model with accountability