final exam Flashcards
(99 cards)
Explain Aristotle’s warning about seeking precision in ethics, that “a well schooled man is one who searches for that degree of precision in each kind of study, which the nature of the subject at hand admits” (Handout8).
Every subject demands a different level of precision and it is not right to demand a lot of precision from all of them.
- Explain Aristotle’s examples of people learning to “become builders by building houses and harpists by playing the harp” how this applies to learning to be virtuous (Handout8).
We become virtuous by being virtuous.
- Explain Aristotle’s notion of seeking the “median and the best course” regarding things like “fear, confidence, desire, [and] anger” (Handout8).
We can feel emotions in excess, deficiency, and median. By experiencing emotions at the right time, toward the right objects, the right people, and for the right reason, we find the median. This is the mark of virtue.
- Explain Aristotle’s point that the virtue of courage is a ‘golden mean’ of the passion of confidence, between the vice of excess (recklessness) and the vice of deficiency (cowardice) (Handout8).
If you have too much confidence, you become reckless. If you lack confidence, you become a coward. To be courageous, you need to find a balance between excess and deficiency.
- Explain what Aristotle means by the vice of extravagance in contrast to the virtue of generosity (Handout8).
When it comes to giving and receiving money, generosity is the mean. Extravagance is the excess and stinginess is the deficiency.
- Explain how “apathy” or a lack of anger can sometimes be a vice, according to Aristotle (Handout8).
This man is deficient in gentleness. Apathy is his vice.
- What are the virtuous mean and the two vices associated with “pleasantness in amusement” (i.e. how fun you are in social settings) (Handout8).
The virtuous mean is being witty. The excess is buffoonery and the deficiency is being a boor.
- Explain Carol Gilligan’s distinction between a “voice of care” and a “voice of justice” as a matter of two different orientations toward ethics (Carse, 6).
The justice orientation recognizes that moral judgements are derived from abstract and universal principles, is dispassionate, and emphasizes individuals rights, equality, and reciprocity in our relationships. The care orientation is not impartial, understands moral judgements as situational, involves empathy and concern, and emphasizes responsibility in our relationships to others.
- Explain the feminist critique of detachment and impartiality in moral thinking and the view that an “impartial observer is disqualified rather than legitimated as a competent moral judge” (Carse, 8-9).
Detachment and impartiality make it so that we cannot empathize with others or recognize their individual personhood. The care orientation claims that we cannot make moral judgments or moral choices without being attentive to identity and relationship.
- Explain the concern that impartiality “cannot always inform us sufficiently about how to respond to others” (Carse, 10).
If we are impartial, we cannot understand what that individual needs because thor personhood is not recognized.
- Explain critique of an ethics of principles that “Recognizing that a general principle or rule is relevant to the situation at hand, and knowing how it is fittingly to be acted upon, requires a capacity for discernment that is distinct from, and presupposed by, the application of principles themselves” (Carse, 11).
You must know how to appropriately apply principles, not just know what it is. Context matters.
- Explain the notion of a sensitivity to particular features of the context and to other people and how this calls for a “moral capacity which can be developed and […] is not itself principle-governed” (Carse, 12).
Principles require nuance and sensitivity that evolve with experience.
- Explain the distinction in the claim that “well-cultivated emotion” is necessary for both “moral discernment” (e.g. discerning the needs of others) and “moral response” (e.g. responding to these needs) (Carse, 13).
You have to understand emotions well yourself in order to understand the needs of others and how to respond to them.
- Explain the distinction between the motive of an action and the manner of an action, e.g. between acting out of sympathy and acting in ways that express sympathy (Carse, 14).
The motive is why someone does it while the manner is how. It is important to be sympathetic but also to behave sympathetically.
- Explain the critique that an ethics that presupposes relationships between equals will emphasize “mutual non-interference” that can “threaten us with neglect and isolation especially if we are dependent or relatively powerless, like the very young, the very old, or the sick” (Carse, 16).
If someone has a right to something, no one should impede their pursuit of it and vice-versa, leading to mutual non-interference. However, with vulnerable populations, non-interference can threaten them with neglect because they are dependent on others.
- Explain the distinction between “the principle of beneficence” and the “care orientation” (Carse, 19).
The care orientation emphasized sympathy and compassion. Beneficence emphasizes a love of humanity to promote the welfare of others.
- Explain the point that “a full account of the virtues of caretaking would need to spell out conceptions of proper self-regard – or care for oneself – as protection against self-effacement or problematic self-denial and as a precondition of sound caring for others (Carse, 24).
You must practice self-care in order to avoid self-sacrifice or self-denial.
- Explain the distinction between “technical” errors, “judgmental” errors, and “normative errors” and why the third kind is thought to be worse than the other two (P, 34).
Technical error: is when a profession follows their responsibilities conscientiously but their training falls short for the task required.
Judgemental error: when a conscientious profession develops and follows an incorrect strategy.
A normative error: when a professional violates codes of conduct or fails to possess a moral skill.
Technical and judgemental errors are errors made in good faith while a normative error indicates a defect in character.
- Explain the example of how a doctor or a nurse could act with the virtues of kindness and loyalty and yet nonetheless be acting unethically (P, 35).
A nurse could fail to report a coworker acting unethically in order to be kind and loyal, but puts patients in harm’s way. Virtues need to be accompanied with an understanding of what deserves it.
- Explain how the virtue of compassion can lead to “emotional burnout” and how medical and nursing education can counteract this problem (P, 39).
Compassion can sometimes cloud judgement and lead to impassioned decisions and emotional burnout rises.
- Explain the role of critical thinking in the virtue of conscientiousness, and how “moral indignation and outrage” can have a valuable role (P, 43).
To be conscientious, one has to be able to think critically about a situation. Moral indignation and outrage can be virtuous under certain circumstances like a doctor fighting an insurance company to help their patient receive care.
- Explain what is meant by “conscientious refusals” and the worry about “banning or greatly restricting conscientious refusals” (P, 43-4).
Conscientious refusals are refusing to do something that doesn’t align with your own beliefs. Banning or restricting conscientious refusals raises worries about balancing professionals’ and patients’ rights.
- How could a “right action” nonetheless not be a “virtuous action”? What are the three criteria for a virtuous action according to Aristotle (P, 410)?
The right action could lack virtue if it is done in the wrong state of mind. To be virtuous, a person must know they are committing a virtuous act, he must decide on the,, and they must do them from a firm and unchanging state.
- Explain the point that the “friend who acts only from obligation lacks the virtue of friendliness, and in the absence of this virtue, the relationship lacks the moral quality of friendship” (P, 412).
A person who acts out of obligation, and not a desire to be friendly due to valuing friendship, lacks the moral quality of friendship.