Knowledge Flashcards

(45 cards)

1
Q

What is the classical account of knowledge?

A

S knows that P iff:
i) P is true
ii) S believes that P
iii) S is justified in believing that P

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Suppose you believe that P, and D is some potential defect in your belief that P. What are the conservative, liberal and intermediate stances?

A

The most conservative stance says that to be justified in believing P, you need to also have some (independent) reasons for believing that your beliefs lack that defect, that is, for believing not-D.

A much more liberal stance says that, so long as you lack evidence that D, you can be justified in believing P.

The intermediate stance says that, to be justified in believing P, it just has to be true that your beliefs lack the defect D.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

What is a counterexample to suggest that belief is not necessary for knowledge?

A

A schoolboy is taking a quiz. One question reads “When was the Battle of Hastings?” He remembers studying about Hastings and some battle, but he has no idea when it happened. But “1066” looks good, so he chooses that. And so on for the rest of the quiz. As it turns out, he gets a score of 95% on the test. He knew more than he thought.

Some philosophers would describe this case like this: “The boy knew what the right answers were, he just didn’t believe them.” If they’re right, then this is a case of knowledge without belief.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

What is an epistemically justified belief? (Pryor)

A

There must be good reasons for the belief, reasons which are a good indicator that the belief is true. S must also believe that P for those reasons.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

What does it mean for evidence for P to be defeasible?

A

It must be possible for new evidence to emerge that would make not-P more likely than P.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

What is the infallibilist position?

A

In order to know that P, you have to have evidence that guarantees that P is true, or makes you infallible about P.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

State the first Gettier case.

A

Suppose that Smith and Jones have applied for a certain job. And suppose that Smith has strong evidence for the following conjunctive proposition: d) Jones is the man who will get the job, and Jones has ten coins in his pocket. Smith’s evidence for (d) might be that the president of the company assured him that Jones would in the end be selected, and that he, Smith, had counted the coins in Jones’s pocket ten minutes ago. Proposition (d) entails: (e) The man who will get the job has ten coins in his pocket. Let us suppose that Smith sees the entailment from (d) to (e), and accepts (e) on the grounds of (d), for which he has strong evidence. In this case, Smith is clearly justified in believing that (e) is true. But imagine, further, that unknown to Smith, he himself, not Jones, will get the job. And, also, unknown to Smith, he himself has ten coins in his pocket. Proposition (e) is then true, though proposition (d), from which Smith inferred (e), is false. In our example, then, all of the following are true: (i) (e) is true, (ii) Smith believes that (e) is true, and (iii) Smith is justified in believing that (e) is true. But it is equally clear that Smith does not know that (e) is true; for (e) is true in virtue of the number of coins in Smith’s pocket, while Smith does not know how many coins are in Smith’s pocket, and bases his belief in (e) on a count of the coins in Jones’s pocket, whom he falsely believes to be the man who will get the job.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

State the example of a Gettier case from the Indian philosopher Dharmottara in 770 CE.

A

A fire has just been lit to roast some meat. The fire hasn’t started sending up any smoke, but the smell of the meat has attracted a cloud of insects. From a distance, an observer sees the dark swarm above the horizon and mistakes it for smoke. ‘There’s a fire burning at that spot,’ the distant observer says.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

What is the counterexample that exposed a problem with Goldman’s causal account of knowledge?

A

Suppose you are driving through a region that contains a lot of fake barns: mere wooden fronts that just look like barns from the road. You have no reason to suspect this is the case. To your left you see something that looks like a barn, so you believe “That’s a barn.” In fact, it is a barn. By sheer luck, it is one of the few barns in the region. There is nothing wrong with the causal history of your belief. Your belief that you are looking at a barn is appropriately related to the fact that there is a barn, via perception.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Which counterexample can be reapplied to challenge the ‘ruling out false-steps approach’?

A

The fake-barn example does not involve any false beliefs.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

How might considerations of defeasibility resolve the Gettier problem?

A

Knowledge can be ruled out in cases in which there is information ‘out there’ which would defeat the justification for the belief. In each of the Gettier cases, there is this information ‘out there’ (Smith will get the job, Jones does not own a Ford, you are driving through fake barn county) which would defeat the justification.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Give a counterexample that undermines the defeasibility consideration.

A

You see Tom hide a book underneath his jacket and sneak out of the library. On the basis of this, you form the justified belief that Tom stole a library book. As it happens, your belief is true. However, unbeknownst to you, Tom’s mother was going around today telling people that Tom was thousands of miles away, and that Tom’s evil twin John was visiting NY. The fact that Tom’s mother said this is a potentially defeating piece of evidence. If you were to learn of it, it would defeat your justification for believing that Tom stole the book. However, as it turns out, it really was Tom who stole the book. Tom has no twin brother and his mother is a compulsive liar.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

How might the defeasibility criteria be saved and why is this unsucessful?

A

You know that P iff you have a justified true belief that P, and there’s no true information “out there” in the world that would defeat your justification for P, were you to learn of it–unless there’s also some second piece of information that would counteract that defeater.

However, this ultimately fails to explain any Gettier cases. This is because in Gettier cases, P is true, so there is always information ‘out there’ that would defeat the initial defeater. For example, the true information that Smith has ten coins in his pocket.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

How would considerations of defeasibility and ruling out false steps be formally added to the classical account?

A

Their individual contributions would be added as necessary conditions alongside the classical account.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Why does Goldman believe that Gettier cases do not count as knowledge?

A

The one thing that seems to be missing in this example is a causal connection between the fact that makes p true [or simply: the fact that p] and Smith’s belief of p. The requirement of such a causal connection is what I wish to add to the traditional analysis.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

What is Goldman’s causal account?

A

For S to know that P, S’s belief must be appropriately causally connected to the state of affairs corresponding to P.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

What are common examples of appropriate causal connections that Goldman highlights?

A

Perception, testimony, memory.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

What is the obscurium per obscurius objection to Goldman’s causal account?

A

It explains the obscure by what is more obscure. For example, it is not clear how the numbers 2 and 3 cause us to know that they make 5, or the universal proposition that all humans are mortal causes us to know this fact.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

What is an objection to Goldman’s causal account (with the example of a lottery)?

A

If I have bought 1 of 1000 lottery tickets, I can form a belief that I will not win the lottery. Suppose that my ticket does not win the lottery. It does not seem clear how the fact that I did not win the lottery caused my belief, rather than just an understanding of probability.

20
Q

Does Goldman argue that justification is necessary for knowledge?

A

Goldman dispenses with the justification condition. S can know that P even if the original justification has been forgotten, as long as there is the appropriate causal connection. For example, I can know that Abraham Lincoln was born in 1809, even if I can no longer recall that I found the information from a reliable encyclopedia.

21
Q

What are some examples of unreliable belief-forming processes according to Goldman?

A

Confused reasoning, wishful thinking, reliance on emotional attachment, mere hunch, hasty generalization.

22
Q

What are some examples of reliable belief-forming processes according to Goldman?

A

Standard perceptual processes, remembering, good reasoning, introspection.

23
Q

How does Goldman define define reliability?

A

The tendency of a process to produce beliefs that are true rather than false.

24
Q

How does Goldman define ‘tendency’?

A

It could either refer to ‘actual long-term tendency’ or to a ‘propensity’. Our notion of justification is vague on this front, so Goldman allows vagueness in this part of his account too.

25
How does Goldman define a process?
A functional mapping from inputs to outputs, where the outputs are beliefs.
26
What is Goldman's initial account of justification?
If S's believing p at t results from a reliable cognitive belief-forming process (or set of processes), then S's belief in p at t is justified.
27
What does it mean for a process to be conditionally reliable?
A sufficient proportion of its output-beliefs are true given that its input-beliefs are true. E.g. memory is reliable, given that the beliefs which are being recalled are true.
28
What is Goldman's updated account that deals with this notion of conditional reliability?
6a: If S's belief in p at t results from a belief-independent process that is unconditionally reliable, then S's belief in p at t is justified. 6b: If S's belief in p at t results from a belief-dependent process that is conditionally reliable, and if the beliefs on which this process operates in producing S's belief in p at t are themselves justified, then S's belief in p at t is justified.
29
What is the final account of justification that Goldman explicates?
(10) If S's belief in p at t results from a reliable cognitive process, and there is no reliable or conditionally reliable process available to S which, had it been used by S in addition to the process actually used, would have resulted in S's not believing p at t, then S's belief in p at t is justified.
30
Offer some different descriptions of the process of looking outside the window and seeing that it is raining.
the process of forming beliefs on the basis of perception the process of forming beliefs on the basis of vision the process of forming beliefs about the weather on the basis of looking out a window the process of forming a belief that it's raining on the basis of seeing droplets splashing on the pavement
31
Who raised the generality concern about process reliabilism?
Richard Feldman
32
What is the problem if the process is described too generally?
It draws 'no distinction' between beliefs that clearly have very different epistemic statuses. For instance, my visually-based belief about the gender of a distant figure seen through a dirty window-pane is obviously less justified than my visually-based belief about the shape of a coin I scrutinize closely in good light.
33
What is the problem if the process is described too specifically?
If the process is extremely specific, then there might have only ever been one belief formed by it--namely, my current belief that it's raining. Whether or not it tends to produce true beliefs (is reliable) depends only on whether this single belief is true. Hence, whether my belief is justified depends entirely on whether it is true. This seems an unacceptable result as there is a difference between a belief being justified and a belief being true.
34
What is the belief regulation concern for reliablism?
Most of the time, we do not know what the truth is. Instead, we regulate our beliefs by choosing the beliefs which are justified. However, if reliabilism is the account of justification, we do not have access to the information that determines whether our beliefs are justified. Therefore, it does not seem that justification can provide this important function under the reliabilist account.
35
What is the epistemic regress problem?
The important point about inferential justification, however, is that if the justificandum belief is to be genuinely justified by the proffered argument, then the belief that provides the premise of the argument must itself be justified in some fashion. This premise belief might of course itself be inferentially justified, but this would only raise a new issue of justification with respect to the premise(s) of this new justificatory argument, and so on, so that empirical knowledge is threatened by an infinite and seemingly vicious regress of epistemic justification, with a thoroughgoing skepticism as the eventual outcome. So long as each new step of justification is inferential, it appears that justification can never be completed, indeed can never really even get started, and hence that there is no justification and no knowledge. Thus the epistemic regress problem. (Bonjour)
36
What is epistemic justification? (Paul)
Beliefs that are epistemically justified are the beliefs that we ought to have.
37
What is foundationalism?
Foundationalism: the view that the epistemic regress terminates by reaching empirical beliefs (a) that are genuinely justified, but (b) whose justification is not inferentially dependent on that of any further empirical beliefs.
38
How does Laurence Bonjour define epistemic justification?
Accept only beliefs for which there is adequate reason to think they are true. To accept beliefs on some other basis is to violate one's epistemic duty- to be, one might say, epistemically irresponsible.
39
What is Bonjour's argument against foundationalism as a solution to the regress problem?
Thus if basic beliefs are to provide a suitable foundation for empirical knowledge, if inference from them is to be the sole basis for the justification of other empirical beliefs, then that feature, whatever it may be, in virtue of which an empirical belief qualifies as basic, must also constitute an adequate reason for thinking that the belief is true. And now if we assume, plausibly enough, that the person for whom a belief is basic must himself possess the justification for that belief if his acceptance of it is to be epistemically rational or responsible, and thus apparently that he must believe with justification both (a) that the belief has the feature in question and (b) that beliefs having that feature are likely to be true, then we get the result that this belief is not basic after all, since its justification depends on that of these other beliefs. If this result is correct, then foundationalism is untenable as a solution to the regress problem.
40
What is the revised reliabilist account that Bonjour proposes?
A belief is justified if it is formed via a reliable belief-forming process and it satisfies these conditions as well: i) the absence of any reasons against the particular belief in question ii) the believer in question has no cogent reasons, either relative to his own case or in general, for thinking that the belief-forming process is not reliable
41
What is Bonjour's 'Norman' case?
Case IV. Norman, under certain conditions that usually obtain, is a completely reliable clairvoyant with respect to certain kinds of subject matter. He possesses no evidence or reasons of any kind for or against the general possibility of such a cognitive power, or for or against the thesis that he possesses it. One day Norman comes to believe that the President is in New York City, though he has no evidence either for or against this belief. In fact the belief is true and results from his clairvoyant power, under circumstances in which it is completely reliable.
42
Does it matter whether Norman believes he has this clairvoyant power (in terms of whether he is epistemically justified)?
No. He has no reason to believe that he has the power of clairvoyance. If he does not believe this, he has no reason to believe that the president is in New York City. He is thus epistemically irrational and irresponsible in either case.
43
Why does Bonjour think that his Norman case is a devastating objection to externalism?
Norman's acceptance of the belief about the President's whereabouts is epistemically irrational and irresponsible, and thereby unjustified. The reliability of the belief-forming process is not available to Norman, so that from his point of view, it is subjectively irrational.
44
How else does Bonjour attack the externalist position?
A moral analogy- whether an action is morally justified requires a reflection of the subjective viewpoint of the person involved. To act with no consideration of the consequences (assuming utilitarianism), cannot be morally justified, even if the consequences are the best overall. Second, we may appeal to the connection between knowledge and rational action. Suppose that Norman, in addition to the clairvoyant belief described earlier, also believes that the Attorney-General is in Chicago. This latter belief, however, is not a clairvoyant belief but is based upon ordinary empirical evidence in Norman's possession, evidence strong enough to give the belief some fairly high degree of reasonableness, but not strong enough to satisfy the requirement for knowledge. Suppose further that Norman finds himself in a situation where he is forced to bet a very large amount, perhaps even his life or the life of someone else, on the whereabouts of either the President or the Attorney-General. Given his epistemic situation as described, which bet is it more reasonable for him to make? It seems relatively clear that it is more reasonable for him to bet the Attorney-General is in Chicago than to bet that the President is in New York City. But then we have the paradoxical result that from the externalist standpoint it is more rational to act on a merely reasonable belief than to act on one that is adequately justifed to qualify as knowledge (and which in fact is knowledge). It is very hard to see how this could be so. If greater epistemic reasonableness does not carry with it greater reasonableness of action, then it becomes most difficult to see why it should be sought in the first place.
45
How does Pryor characterise and criticise Bonjour's argument?
1. Your belief was reliably formed, but you have no evidence that it was. 2. Hence, from your subjective perspective, it would seem an accident if your belief turned out to be true. 3. Hence, your belief is unjustified. On the intermediate or liberal account, there is no clear interpretation where 2 follows from 1, and supports 3.