Unit 3: Goodman, Zero/Sainsbury, Kant Flashcards
(30 cards)
a formal theory of confirmation
- a formal theory of good inductive reasoning
- how do particular repeated observations confirm a generalization?
- the idea that relations of confirmation might be modified in style of deductive logic
Formal theory of confirmation…deductive to inductive
- example of deductive logic
- all humans are mortal
- socrates is human
- C: socrates is mortal
- notice, we only had to refer to the form and not the actual content
- attempt to argue that inductive relations and reasoning or arguments might be given as a formal theory as well
- Goal: to formulate inductive logic like deductive logic, borrowing deductive logic whenever possible
deductive
logical reasoning
inductive
evidential reasoning
the ravens problem
- observation: repeatedly observe black ravens
- hypothesis: all ravens are black
- logical equivalence/contrapositive:
- if its a raven, then its black if and only if for all x if not black it is not a raven
- Problem: all ravens are black, if and only if all non black things are not ravens
- evidence for hypothesis that all nonblack things are not ravens
- swan f is always white, something not black, not raven evidence must also support its logial equivalent
- so, swan f that is white, confirms all ravens are black
goodman problem
- “indoor orinthology”
- instances of generalization confirm the generalization of its equivalent
- ridiculous, because we can’t investigate the color of ravens without going outside
- ie brown shoe example
- induction should require some observation
what the raven’s problem shows
- PGS reports a point made by I.J. Good: trouble because comparing one proposition (oberservation) with another (hypothesis)
- a binary analysis of support relations
- a 3 place relation can exhibit disconfirmation
- “confirmation depends on other factors”
- PGS reports another point made by Good
- ordinality and the possibility to confirm or disconfirm
- “depends on the order in which you learn of the properties of an object”
- ordinality and the possibility to confirm or disconfirm
- *Overall the problem shows
- ordinality and the possibility to confirm or disconfirm
the new riddle of induction intro
- formal theories of confirmation and instance confirmation
- deductive: universal instantiation
- all Fs are Gs
- A is an F
- C: A is a G
- inductive: instance, enumerative
- emerald a is green
- emerald b is green
- C: all emeralds are green
- model of FTC of good inductive reasoning after deductive reasoning
- we learn something about the nature of support
- goodman undermines the prospects for not developing this idea
- goodman is NOT arguing that confirmation is impossible or that relations of confirmation dont exist
- hes attacking the idea that a purely formal theory can be successful, there can never be a formal theory of induction and confirmation
- characterized with variables, not with content
- goodman is NOT arguing that confirmation is impossible or that relations of confirmation dont exist
“grue”
- an object is grue IFF it was first oberserved before 2015 and was green, or 2 it was not first observed before 2015 and is blue
- argument is not good because it says emeralds we observe from now on will be blue
- but this argument has exactly the same form as the good inductive argument we saw before
- All observations of emeralds before 2015 confirm both hypotheses
- 1: any yet to be seen emerald is green
- 2: any yet to be seen emerald is blue
- Therfore, FTC does not seem to be possible
the new riddle of induction & suggestions
- q: what exactly is wrong with bad inductive arguments? what makes bad induction bad?
- Suggestions to fix
- restrict such words as grue because they refer to time
- properties words should refer to should be natural kinds (but what is outside of chemical elements?)
- dont employ complex terms, replace with simpler ones
- Brings us to: the curve fitting problem
- do we choose a straight line to fix the curve because its simpler? then it would be wrong!
- Brings us to: the curve fitting problem
Zeno’s background and 2 radical conclusions
- Background
- use of conceptual clarification of calculus and the development of rigorous methods for invetigating the infinite
- challenging fundamental concepts in metaphysics
- the relation of the parts of an object to the whole object, mereology
- problems about the way objects persist through time, persistence
- the nature of space, metaphysics
- abstract qs about exactly how math or geometric concepts can be applied to material objects, from metaphysics to physics
- Claim 1
- there is not more than one thing
- claim 2
- change or motion is not possible
spatial relations and mereology
- spatial relation and parts whole relations
- example: how can 1 thing, a book, be many things: pages, molecues
- answer: its not, the book is not identical to many things, the book just has many parts
- zero attempts to show that the idea that material objects have parts is absurd
- so, we must reject the claim that anything has parts–it is all one thing
- example
- 1: if a book has parts, infinitley many
- 2: if a book has infinite parts, it is infinitley large
- 3: so, if a book has parts it is infinitlyey large
- 4: no book is inifinitley large
- C: no book has parts
Re premis 1: if a book has parts, infinitley many
- if a book has parts, then the region of space it contains has parts, and the book has a part corresponding to every part of space it fills
- so, if a region of space has parts, it has infinitley many parts
Re premis 2: if a book has infinite parts, it is infinitley large
- if a region of space has infinitley many parts, it is infinitley large
- this claim does a lot of work for the argument
- parthood for space requires infinite divisibility
- reasonable, because finite amount of space parts is finitley large
- there is something wrong with this
- a finite region of space contains infinitley many parts
- Q: how do they all fit?, thet are continually getting smaller
- Distinction
- **if, for some finite size, a whole contains infinite parts, none smaller than this size, then the whole is infinitley large
- true: saying 0.5 + 0.5…=infinity (not going to be a finite size)
- if a whole contains infinitley many parts, each of some finite size, then the whole is inifinitley large
- False: they can be smaller than the other ie 0.4 + 0.3 + 0.2…does not equal infinity
- **if, for some finite size, a whole contains infinite parts, none smaller than this size, then the whole is infinitley large
- so, there is no contradiction in the idea that space is divisible. but this does not entail that space, the actual space, actually is infinitley divisible
- reasonable, because finite amount of space parts is finitley large
- premis 2 is false: zenos argument against plurality fails, fails because of of this statement **
- for all we know, space might be granular
- zeno has not given us any reason to think that space is granular
The Racetrack, the dichotomy, sainsbury
- paradox: motion is impossible
- traveling from a to b requires infinitley many journeys
- it is impossible for anything to complete infinite number of journeys
- C: impossible to get from A to B
- C2: points are arbitrary, so all motion is impossible (False)
re premis 1 “traveling from a to b requires infinite journeys”
- which is correct?
passing through all z points is sufficient for reaching z
passing through all the z points is not sufficient for reaching z
both good arguments, both cant be true
objection argument for a: benacerraf: where would the runner be after passing all the z points? nowhere because one might cease to exist after reaching every point but without reaching z ie shrinking genie
argument of a: sainsbury: “there is some discrepancy here between the abstract mathematical space like notions and our notions of physical space”
suppose we divide a line into x, y, and point b
is b in x, y, or both? cannot be in both…
say b is in x, imagine an archer asked to shoot through y without touching x: problem
the point b has to partally compose a line to which it belongs. we need a different notion: one that allowes x and y to touch without overlapping and a boundary that does not itself occupy space
immanuel kant on the reality of space
- on the first ground of the distinction of regions of space
- importance 1768
- contains an ingenous argument for existence of space
- claim defending: absolute space has a reality of its own, independent of the existence of all matter and indeed as the first ground of possibility of the compositness of matter (an ontological claim)
kants reality of space claim
- ontological claim: claim about what exists
- that in addition to particular spatiotemporal relations between materials objects and their parts, there also exists a further thing-space itself
- why is it at all controversial whether space exists?
- it has been debated since the beginning of intellectual thought through today: Gottfried Leibniz and Isaac Newton famously disagreed
an ontological debate on space
- what question is being asked in whether space exists?
- what did leibniz and newton agree on? spatial relations exists
- disagree: what spatial relations are, fundamentally speaking, relations between (ie the nature of spatial relations or of space itself)
newtons absolutism
- newton held that spatial relations between point in space, points of space exist independent of any material objects that occupy the points
- an absolutism about space, or defense of absolute space
- now called substantialism
- Overall: material objects, spatial relations, absolute spatial points (coordinate position)
leibniz relationism
- L held that spatial relations are fundamentally relations between actual or possible material objects
- called relationism
- Overall: material objects, spatial relations
- Kant weighing in on debate: defending newt geometers assume it exists too
absolute space
points on a diagram/plane
relational space
im 5 meters from jack
leibniz and newton agree this exists
the general strategy
- claim: absolute space has a reality of its own, independent of the existence of all matter and indeed as the first ground of the possibility of the compositeness of matter