Arguments Flashcards

1
Q

Hume’s Argument from Illusion

A
  1. The table appears to shrink in size
  2. The table does not in fact change in size
  3. Conclusion 1: the subject perceives an image of the table
  4. Conclusion 2: the subject does not perceive the table
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q
  1. The table appears to shrink in size
    2._________________
  2. Conclusion 1: the subject perceives an image of the table
  3. Conclusion 2: the subject does not perceive the table
A

The table does not in fact change in size

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q
  1. The table appears to shrink in size
  2. The table does not in fact change in size
  3. ______________________
  4. Conclusion 2: the subject does not perceive the table
A

Conclusion 1: the subject perceives an image of the table

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q
  1. ____________________
  2. The table does not in fact change in size
  3. Conclusion 1: the subject perceives an image of the table
  4. Conclusion 2: the subject does not perceive the table
A

The table appears to shrink in size

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q
  1. The table appears to shrink in size
  2. The table does not in fact change in size
  3. Conclusion 1: the subject perceives an image of the table
  4. ________________________
A

Conclusion 2: the subject does not perceive the table

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Contemporary Argument from Illusion

A
  1. Perceptual Illusion: There are cases in which a subject has a perceptual experience as of
    something having a property F, but the external world object perceived by the subject is not
    in fact F.
  2. Phenomenal Principle: If a subject has a perceptual experience as of something having a
    property F, some thing of which the subject is directly aware actually has F.
  3. In the cases described in 1, the external world object the subject perceives is not the F-thing
    of which she is directly aware. [1 & 2]
  4. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness is something other than
    the external world object she perceives. [3]
  5. If we want to claim that illusory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness of different
    sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim. [General Methodological Principle]
  6. For some veridical experiences, there is an illusory experience which from the subject’s point
    of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
  7. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 5. [6]
  8. Absent some other ground, we must say that illusory and veridical experiences involve
    awareness of the same sorts of objects. [5 & 7]
  9. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [4 & 8]
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q
  1. Perceptual Illusion: There are cases in which a subject has a perceptual experience as of
    something having a property F, but the external world object perceived by the subject is not
    in fact F.
  2. Phenomenal Principle: If a subject has a perceptual experience as of something having a
    property F, some thing of which the subject is directly aware actually has F.
  3. ______________________
  4. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness is something other than
    the external world object she perceives. [3]
  5. If we want to claim that illusory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness of different
    sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim. [General Methodological Principle]
  6. For some veridical experiences, there is an illusory experience which from the subject’s point
    of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
  7. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 5. [6]
  8. Absent some other ground, we must say that illusory and veridical experiences involve
    awareness of the same sorts of objects. [5 & 7]
  9. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [4 & 8]
A

In the cases described in 1, the external world object the subject perceives is not the F-thing
of which she is directly aware. [1 & 2]

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q
  1. Perceptual Illusion: There are cases in which a subject has a perceptual experience as of
    something having a property F, but the external world object perceived by the subject is not
    in fact F.
  2. Phenomenal Principle: If a subject has a perceptual experience as of something having a
    property F, some thing of which the subject is directly aware actually has F.
  3. In the cases described in 1, the external world object the subject perceives is not the F-thing
    of which she is directly aware. [1 & 2]
  4. ___________________
  5. If we want to claim that illusory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness of different
    sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim. [General Methodological Principle]
  6. For some veridical experiences, there is an illusory experience which from the subject’s point
    of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
  7. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 5. [6]
  8. Absent some other ground, we must say that illusory and veridical experiences involve
    awareness of the same sorts of objects. [5 & 7]
  9. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [4 & 8]
A

In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness is something other than
the external world object she perceives. [3]

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q
  1. Perceptual Illusion: There are cases in which a subject has a perceptual experience as of
    something having a property F, but the external world object perceived by the subject is not
    in fact F.
  2. Phenomenal Principle: If a subject has a perceptual experience as of something having a
    property F, some thing of which the subject is directly aware actually has F.
  3. In the cases described in 1, the external world object the subject perceives is not the F-thing
    of which she is directly aware. [1 & 2]
  4. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness is something other than
    the external world object she perceives. [3]
  5. _______________________
  6. For some veridical experiences, there is an illusory experience which from the subject’s point
    of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
  7. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 5. [6]
  8. Absent some other ground, we must say that illusory and veridical experiences involve
    awareness of the same sorts of objects. [5 & 7]
  9. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [4 & 8]
A

If we want to claim that illusory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness of different
sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim. [General Methodological Principle]

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q
  1. Perceptual Illusion: There are cases in which a subject has a perceptual experience as of
    something having a property F, but the external world object perceived by the subject is not
    in fact F.
  2. Phenomenal Principle: If a subject has a perceptual experience as of something having a
    property F, some thing of which the subject is directly aware actually has F.
  3. In the cases described in 1, the external world object the subject perceives is not the F-thing
    of which she is directly aware. [1 & 2]
  4. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness is something other than
    the external world object she perceives. [3]
  5. If we want to claim that illusory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness of different
    sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim. [General Methodological Principle]
  6. __________________________
  7. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 5. [6]
  8. Absent some other ground, we must say that illusory and veridical experiences involve
    awareness of the same sorts of objects. [5 & 7]
  9. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [4 & 8]
A

For some veridical experiences, there is an illusory experience which from the subject’s point
of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

What is the conclusion of the Contemporary Argument from Illusion

A

Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
independent) external world objects.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

1) If something appears F to some observers and not-F to others, then it is not
inherently/really/in itself F.

Burnyeat argues this is equivalent to

A

2) If something is inherently/really/in itself F, then it appears F to all observers or it appears
not-F to all.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

2) If something is inherently/really/in itself F, then it appears F to all observers or it appears
not-F to all.

Burnyeat argues this is equivalent to

A

1) If something appears F to some observers and not-F to others, then it is not
inherently/really/in itself F.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Argument against Phenomenal Internalism (3)

A

i. Introspective knowledge of the phenomenal character of perceptual experience must
be both certain and infallible.

ii. If a fact does not wholly depend upon a subject’s intrinsic features (e.g. it concerns
some external object), knowledge of the fact is not both certain and infallible.

iii. Either introspection provides no knowledge of phenomenal character, or B is true.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

McDowell’s argument for representationalism (3)

A
  1. it would be rational for a subject to form a belief only if the content of her belief would bear a suitable relation to contents of those speech acts or mental states in response to which she formed the belief.
  2. It is often rational to form beliefs in response to sensory experience (e.g. to believe that
    something is round in response to seeing a round object).
  3. Only representationalism affords representational content a fundamental role in sensory
    experience
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Argument for representationalism from Vision Science (3)

A
  1. According to our best vision science, we perceive the world in virtue of perceptual processing
    that constructs and manipulates representations, and these representations encode
    information about distal or ‘external’ properties (e.g. colours, shapes, etc.).
  2. A right account of perception must respect our best science of perception [Methodological
    Naturalism]
    So,
  3. Respecting our best vision science requires that visual experiences are representations that
    encode information about external properties.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q
  1. According to our best vision science, we perceive the world in virtue of perceptual processing
    that constructs and manipulates representations, and these representations encode
    information about distal or ‘external’ properties (e.g. colours, shapes, etc.).
  2. ______________________
    So,
  3. Respecting our best vision science requires that visual experiences are representations that
    encode information about external properties.
A

A right account of perception must respect our best science of perception [Methodological
Naturalism]

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q
  1. ____________________(e.g. colours, shapes, etc.).
  2. A right account of perception must respect our best science of perception [Methodological
    Naturalism]
    So,
  3. Respecting our best vision science requires that visual experiences are representations that
    encode information about external properties.
A

According to our best vision science, we perceive the world in virtue of perceptual processing
that constructs and manipulates representations, and these representations encode
information about distal or ‘external’ properties

19
Q
  1. According to our best vision science, we perceive the world in virtue of perceptual processing
    that constructs and manipulates representations, and these representations encode
    information about distal or ‘external’ properties (e.g. colours, shapes, etc.).
  2. A right account of perception must respect our best science of perception [Methodological
    Naturalism]
    So,
  3. __________________________
A

Respecting our best vision science requires that visual experiences are representations that
encode information about external properties.

20
Q

Campbell’s argument for Naive Realism (6)

A
  1. It is a defining characteristic of thought-like representational contents that they are accessible
    to the subject in multiple ways (for example, a single proposition might be accessible as the
    meaning of a sentence; as the content of a belief; as the conclusion entailed by a series of
    premisses….)
  2. If sensory experiences are just a class of mental states with thought-like representational
    contents, the representational content of a sensory experience is accessible to the subject in
    multiple ways: it is a representational content that can be shared by mental states that are not
    sensory experiences.
  3. If the representational content of perceptual experience is accessible to the subject in multiple
    ways, having a sensory experience is just one among many ways of being in a mental state that
    has this kind of representational content.
  4. The claim that sensory experiences are a class of mental states with thought-like representational contents is inconsistent with the claim that perception plays an essential role
    in enabling us to think about external world objects.
  5. Naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think about
    external world objects.
  6. Only naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think
    about external world objects.
21
Q
  1. It is a defining characteristic of thought-like representational contents that they are accessible
    to the subject in multiple ways (for example, a single proposition might be accessible as the
    meaning of a sentence; as the content of a belief; as the conclusion entailed by a series of
    premisses….)
  2. If sensory experiences are just a class of mental states with thought-like representational
    contents, the representational content of a sensory experience is accessible to the subject in
    multiple ways: it is a representational content that can be shared by mental states that are not
    sensory experiences.
  3. ______________________
  4. The claim that sensory experiences are a class of mental states with thought-like representational contents is inconsistent with the claim that perception plays an essential role
    in enabling us to think about external world objects.
  5. Naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think about
    external world objects.
  6. Only naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think
    about external world objects.
A

If the representational content of perceptual experience is accessible to the subject in multiple
ways, having a sensory experience is just one among many ways of being in a mental state that
has this kind of representational content.

22
Q
  1. It is a defining characteristic of thought-like representational contents that they are accessible
    to the subject in multiple ways (for example, a single proposition might be accessible as the
    meaning of a sentence; as the content of a belief; as the conclusion entailed by a series of
    premisses….)
  2. If sensory experiences are just a class of mental states with thought-like representational
    contents, the representational content of a sensory experience is accessible to the subject in
    multiple ways: it is a representational content that can be shared by mental states that are not
    sensory experiences.
  3. If the representational content of perceptual experience is accessible to the subject in multiple
    ways, having a sensory experience is just one among many ways of being in a mental state that
    has this kind of representational content.
  4. The claim that sensory experiences are a class of mental states with thought-like representational contents is inconsistent with the claim that perception plays an essential role
    in enabling us to think about external world objects.
  5. Naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think about
    external world objects.
  6. ________________________
A

Only naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think
about external world objects.

23
Q
  1. It is a defining characteristic of thought-like representational contents that they are accessible
    to the subject in multiple ways (for example, a single proposition might be accessible as the
    meaning of a sentence; as the content of a belief; as the conclusion entailed by a series of
    premisses….)
  2. If sensory experiences are just a class of mental states with thought-like representational
    contents, the representational content of a sensory experience is accessible to the subject in
    multiple ways: it is a representational content that can be shared by mental states that are not
    sensory experiences.
  3. If the representational content of perceptual experience is accessible to the subject in multiple
    ways, having a sensory experience is just one among many ways of being in a mental state that
    has this kind of representational content.
  4. ________________________
  5. Naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think about
    external world objects.
  6. Only naïve realists can explain how perception plays an essential role in enabling us to think
    about external world objects.
A

The claim that sensory experiences are a class of mental states with thought-like representational contents is inconsistent with the claim that perception plays an essential role
in enabling us to think about external world objects.

24
Q

Argument from Hallucination

A
  1. Perceptual Hallucination
  2. Phenomenal Principle:
    So,
  3. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness cannot be an external
    world object with which she in perceptual contact. [1 & 2]
    But,
  4. If we want to claim that hallucinatory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness
    of different sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim.
  5. For some veridical experiences, there is a hallucinatory experience which from the
    subject’s point of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
    Hence,
  6. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 4.
    [5]
    As a result,
  7. Absent some other ground, we must say that hallucinatory and veridical experiences
    involve awareness of the same sorts of objects. [4 & 6]
    So,
  8. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [3 & 7]
25
Q
  1. Perceptual Hallucination
  2. Phenomenal Principle:
    So,
  3. ___________________
    [1 & 2]
    But,
  4. If we want to claim that hallucinatory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness
    of different sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim.
  5. For some veridical experiences, there is a hallucinatory experience which from the
    subject’s point of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
    Hence,
  6. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 4.
    [5]
    As a result,
  7. Absent some other ground, we must say that hallucinatory and veridical experiences
    involve awareness of the same sorts of objects. [4 & 6]
    So,
  8. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [3 & 7]
A

In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness cannot be an external
world object with which she in perceptual contact.

25
Q
  1. Perceptual Hallucination
  2. Phenomenal Principle:
    So,
  3. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness cannot be an external
    world object with which she in perceptual contact. [1 & 2]
    But,
  4. If we want to claim that hallucinatory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness
    of different sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim.
  5. ____________________
    Hence,
  6. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 4.
    [5]
    As a result,
  7. Absent some other ground, we must say that hallucinatory and veridical experiences
    involve awareness of the same sorts of objects. [4 & 6]
    So,
  8. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [3 & 7]
A

For some veridical experiences, there is a hallucinatory experience which from the
subject’s point of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.

26
Q
  1. Perceptual Hallucination
  2. Phenomenal Principle:
    So,
  3. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness cannot be an external
    world object with which she in perceptual contact. [1 & 2]
    But,
  4. If we want to claim that hallucinatory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness
    of different sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim.
  5. For some veridical experiences, there is a hallucinatory experience which from the
    subject’s point of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
    Hence,
  6. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 4.
    [5]
    As a result,
  7. Absent some other ground, we must say that hallucinatory and veridical experiences
    involve awareness of the same sorts of objects. [4 & 6]
    So,
  8. _______________________ [3 & 7]
A

Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
independent) external world objects.

27
Q
  1. Perceptual Hallucination
  2. Phenomenal Principle:
    So,
  3. In the cases described at 1, the direct object of a subject’s awareness cannot be an external
    world object with which she in perceptual contact. [1 & 2]
    But,
  4. If we want to claim that hallucinatory and veridical experiences involve direct awareness
    of different sorts of objects, we need a proper reason to believe this claim.
  5. For some veridical experiences, there is a hallucinatory experience which from the
    subject’s point of view is indistinguishable from the veridical experience.
    Hence,
  6. How things seem from a subject’s point of view provides no grounds for the claim at 4.
    [5]
    As a result,
  7. _____________________[4 & 6]
    So,
  8. Veridical perceptual experience does not involve direct awareness of (presumably mind-
    independent) external world objects. [3 & 7]
A

Absent some other ground, we must say that hallucinatory and veridical experiences
involve awareness of the same sorts of objects.

28
Q

Martin argues that Naive Realism is inconsistent with two assumptions:

A
  1. Common kind assumption
  2. Experiential Naturalism
29
Q

Martin’s Argument against Naive Realism

A
  1. When a subject perceives a raspberry bush, her experience has the bush as a mind-independent
    object of (non-representational) awareness: she is aware of a bush whose existence does not
    depend on her awareness of it, and this awareness could not obtain in the absence of the bush
    [Naive Realism]
    Applying (A) to 1:
  2. Whatever kind of experience the subject undergoes when she perceives the bush, the very
    same kind of experience could occur when she is merely hallucinating. [From (A) and 1]
    But
  3. The experience the subject has when hallucinating must have a sufficient physical cause [From
    2 and (B)]
    So
  4. Either that experience includes awareness of an object for whose existence the experience is
    sufficient, or the experience does not involve awareness of an object [From 3]
    Question: why does Experiential Naturalism generate this result? See what Martin says
    at the top of p. 41.
    However,
  5. If an experience has an object of awareness for whose existence the experience is sufficient,
    then that object is mind-dependent [From def. of mind-dependence]
    Now apply 4 and 5 to 2:
  6. Either the subject who perceives the bush thereby perceives a mind-dependent object, or she
    is not aware of an object.
30
Q
  1. When a subject perceives a raspberry bush, her experience has the bush as a mind-independent
    object of (non-representational) awareness: she is aware of a bush whose existence does not
    depend on her awareness of it, and this awareness could not obtain in the absence of the bush
    [Naive Realism]
    Applying (A) to 1:
  2. Whatever kind of experience the subject undergoes when she perceives the bush, the very
    same kind of experience could occur when she is merely hallucinating. [From (A) and 1]
    But
  3. The experience the subject has when hallucinating must have a sufficient physical cause [From
    2 and (B)]
    So
  4. Either that experience includes awareness of an object for whose existence the experience is
    sufficient, ________________[From 3]
  5. If an experience has an object of awareness for whose existence the experience is sufficient,
    then that object is mind-dependent [From def. of mind-dependence]
    Now apply 4 and 5 to 2:
  6. Either the subject who perceives the bush thereby perceives a mind-dependent object, or she
    is not aware of an object.
A

or the experience does not involve awareness of an object

31
Q
  1. When a subject perceives a raspberry bush, her experience has the bush as a mind-independent
    object of (non-representational) awareness: she is aware of a bush whose existence does not
    depend on her awareness of it, and this awareness could not obtain in the absence of the bush
    [Naive Realism]
    Applying (A) to 1:
  2. Whatever kind of experience the subject undergoes when she perceives the bush, the very
    same kind of experience could occur when she is merely hallucinating. [From (A) and 1]
    But
  3. The experience the subject has when hallucinating must have a sufficient physical cause [From
    2 and (B)]
    So
  4. Either that experience includes awareness of an object for whose existence the experience is
    sufficient, or the experience does not involve awareness of an object [From 3]
    However,
  5. If an experience has an object of awareness for whose existence the experience is sufficient,
    then that object is mind-dependent [From def. of mind-dependence]
    Now apply 4 and 5 to 2:
  6. __________________
A

Either the subject who perceives the bush thereby perceives a mind-dependent object, or she
is not aware of an object.

32
Q
  1. When a subject perceives a raspberry bush, her experience has the bush as a mind-independent
    object of (non-representational) awareness: she is aware of a bush whose existence does not
    depend on her awareness of it, and this awareness could not obtain in the absence of the bush
    [Naive Realism]
    Applying (A) to 1:
  2. Whatever kind of experience the subject undergoes when she perceives the bush, the very
    same kind of experience could occur when she is merely hallucinating. [From (A) and 1]
    But
  3. The experience the subject has when hallucinating must have a sufficient physical cause [From
    2 and (B)]
    So
  4. Either that experience includes awareness of an object for whose existence the experience is
    sufficient, or the experience does not involve awareness of an object [From 3]
    However,
  5. ____________________ [From def. of mind-dependence]
    Now apply 4 and 5 to 2:
  6. Either the subject who perceives the bush thereby perceives a mind-dependent object, or she
    is not aware of an object.
A

If an experience has an object of awareness for whose existence the experience is sufficient,
then that object is mind-dependent

33
Q
  1. When a subject perceives a raspberry bush, her experience has the bush as a mind-independent
    object of (non-representational) awareness: she is aware of a bush whose existence does not depend on her awareness of it, and ____________________________
    [Naive Realism]
    Applying (A) to 1:
  2. Whatever kind of experience the subject undergoes when she perceives the bush, the very same kind of experience could occur when she is merely hallucinating. [From (A) and 1]
    But
  3. The experience the subject has when hallucinating must have a sufficient physical cause [From
    2 and (B)]
    So
  4. Either that experience includes awareness of an object for whose existence the experience is
    sufficient, or the experience does not involve awareness of an object [From 3]
    Question: why does Experiential Naturalism generate this result? See what Martin says
    at the top of p. 41.
    However,
  5. If an experience has an object of awareness for whose existence the experience is sufficient,
    then that object is mind-dependent [From def. of mind-dependence]
    Now apply 4 and 5 to 2:
  6. Either the subject who perceives the bush thereby perceives a mind-dependent object, or she
    is not aware of an object.
A

this awareness could not obtain in the absence of the bush

34
Q

Causal Argument for the Common Kind Assumption

A

i. there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. Possible that C should occur in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment
iii. Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: Where two situations involve the same proximate causal
conditions, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in both
situations.
So,
iv. Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by 1, the same kind of
experience occurs in the situation described at 2. [From i-iii]

35
Q

i. When a subject sees a raspberry bush, there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in
the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. It is nomologically possible—namely possible given the laws of nature—that C should occur
in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment
iii. Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: Where two situations involve the same proximate causal
conditions, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in both
situations.
So,
iv. Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by 1, _______________ [From i-iii]

A

the same kind of
experience occurs in the situation described at 2.

36
Q

i. When a subject sees a raspberry bush, there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in
the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. It is nomologically possible—namely possible given the laws of nature—that C ___________________
iii. Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: Where two situations involve the same proximate causal
conditions, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in both
situations.
So,
iv. Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by 1, the same kind of
experience occurs in the situation described at 2. [From i-iii]

A

should occur
in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment

37
Q

i. When a subject sees a raspberry bush, there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in
the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. It is nomologically possible—namely possible given the laws of nature—that C should occur
in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment
iii. Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: _____________________
So,
iv. Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by 1, the same kind of
experience occurs in the situation described at 2. [From i-iii]

A

Where two situations involve the same proximate causal
conditions, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in both
situations.

38
Q

Reverse Causal Argument

A

i. When a subject sees a raspberry bush, there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in
the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. It is nomologically possible—namely possible given the laws of nature—that C should occur
in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment
iii. Modified Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: Where two situations involve the same
proximate causal conditions, and do not differ in any non-causal conditions for the occurrence
of some kind of effect, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in
both situations.
iv. No non-causal condition obtains in the situation described at (ii)—a situation in which the
subject is victim of hallucination—which does not also obtain in the situation described at
(i)—a case of veridical perception.
So,
v. Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by (ii), it is possible that the
same kind of experience occurs in the situation described at (i).

39
Q

i. When a subject sees a raspberry bush, there is some proximate type of causal condition, C, in
the subject’s body which determined the chance of the occurrence of that even of seeing.
ii. It is nomologically possible—namely possible given the laws of nature—that C should occur
in the subject even if no potential object for perception is present in the subject’s environment
iii. Modified Same Proximate Cause, Same Effect: Where two situations involve the same
proximate causal conditions, and do not differ in any non-causal conditions for the occurrence
of some kind of effect, then the chances for the occurrence of such an effect are the same in
both situations.
iv. No non-causal condition obtains in the situation described at (ii)—a situation in which the
subject is victim of hallucination—which does not also obtain in the situation described at
(i)—a case of veridical perception.
So,
v. ___________________

A

Whatever kind of experience occurs in the situation described by (ii), it is possible that the
same kind of experience occurs in the situation described at (i).

40
Q

Johnston’s Argument Against Negative Epistemic Disjunctivism

A
  1. It is possible to undergo a causally matching hallucination as of a red flower
  2. If a subject has never seen red before, undergoing the hallucination described at 1 would permit her to know, of red, what it is like (e.g., more similar to purple than to green).
    But,
  3. It is impossible to explain our capacity to acquire the knowledge described at 2 from
    hallucination—original de re knowledge of a sensible quality—if negative epistemic
    disjunctivism is true.
    So,
  4. Negative epistemic disjunctivism is false.
41
Q
  1. It is possible to undergo a causally matching hallucination as of a red flower (i.e., a
    hallucination which by Martin’s lights would be indiscriminable through reflection alone
    from a veridical experience of a red flower)
  2. If a subject has never seen red before, undergoing the hallucination described at 1 ______________, what it is like (e.g., more similar to purple than to green).
    But,
  3. It is impossible to explain our capacity to acquire the knowledge described at 2 from
    hallucination—original de re knowledge of a sensible quality—if negative epistemic
    disjunctivism is true.
    So,
  4. Negative epistemic disjunctivism is false.
A

would permit her to know, of red

42
Q
  1. ________________(i.e., a
    hallucination which by Martin’s lights would be indiscriminable through reflection alone
    from a veridical experience of a red flower)
  2. If a subject has never seen red before, undergoing the hallucination described at 1 would permit her to know, of red, what it is like (e.g., more similar to purple than to green).
    But,
  3. It is impossible to explain our capacity to acquire the knowledge described at 2 from
    hallucination—original de re knowledge of a sensible quality—if negative epistemic
    disjunctivism is true.
    So,
  4. Negative epistemic disjunctivism is false.
A

It is possible to undergo a causally matching hallucination as of a red flower

43
Q

How does Sethi preserve naive realism

A

Sethi insists that when
you perceive a red chair, for instance, the instance of redness you perceive depends for its instantiation
upon both your mind and the chair itself, which makes it mind-independent; by contrast, when you
hallucinate a red chair, Sethi allows that while there is an instance of redness, it depends for its
instantiation only upon your mind, and so the instance is mind-dependent