Arguments From Reason Flashcards

1
Q

What is the ontological argument?

A

Ontological arguments claim that God’s existence can be proven a priori - with absolute certainty, using deductive logic. Variations if the ontological argument have been put forward for at least a thousand years - St Anselm’s is one of the earliest. A priori knowledge is m is prior to sense experience.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Who is Anselm?

A

Follower of Plato, Anselm believes that we can know God’s existence purely by reason, a priori. ‘Faith seeking understanding’.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

What are Anselm’s basic idea?

A

Dealing with the ‘fool’: The fool says in his heart that there is no God. Both the theist and the atheist can agree that God exists in the mind. Even the strictest atheist can think of God - if they couldn’t then they wouldn’t understand what they didn’t believe in! We may not be able to fully convince (understand) God, but we do know that we can’t conceive of anything greater than God. Hence, both atheists and theists can agree to this definition of God:

‘That than which nothing greater can be conceived’

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

What is version 1 of Anselm’s ontological argument?

A

P1: God is that than which nothing greater can be conceived. God exists as an idea in our mind.

P2: A being that exists in reality is greater than an imaginary being. Anselm gives the example of a painter, who has an idea of a painting in his/her mind. When the painting exists in reality, it is greater than when it is first an idea in the artist’s mind.

P3: If he only exists in the mind, God would not be the greatest being (this would be a contradiction).

P4: Therefore God must exist in the mind and in reality. Anselm says that the very definition of God proves his existence.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Evaluation of version 1 of Anselm’s ontological argument

A

Premise 1: God is ‘that than which nothing greater can be conceived’.

Criticisms: Is it really possible to come up with a definition of God - a being of whom we have no knowledge nor empirical evidence? Anselm doesn’t define what ‘greatness’ is - greatness means different things to different people. He doesn’t tell us what God is, in himself - his nature. What is God like? Is God the God of Christian beliefs?

Premise 2: A being that exists in reality is greater than a being that exists only in the mind. Anselm gives the example of a painter to demonstrate that it is greater to exist in reality than just in the mind. The painting in his/her mind is greater once it has been painted because now it exists in reality as well as in the mind of the painter.

Criticisms: Gaunilo argues that this is a poor analogy - there is a real difference between the initial idea and the finished product that we can see and experience.

Premise 3: If he only exists in the mind, God would not be the greatest being (thus would be a contradiction). Since anything that exists in reality is greater than things that exist only in the mind, something existing in reality would be greater than God. That is a contradiction, or mistake in reasoning, because God is that than which nothing greater can be conceived.

Criticism: To accept the definition of God but reject the conclusion he exists is a contradiction! It is an illogical, absurd claim to say that God does not exist.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

What is Anselm’s conclusion?

A

God must exist in reality. We are led logically to conclude, a priori, that God exists in reality. The fool fails to believe only because he hasn’t considered the true definition of God. Once he accepts Anselm’s definition then he has to accept that God exists.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Strengths of version 1 of Anselm’s argument

A
  • Atheists and theists do in fact have a sense and understanding of God in mind.
  • God does exist in our mind. Innate sense of the divine.
  • If he only exists in the mind, God would not be the greatest being.
  • Mostly coherent.
  • A priori knowledge links with our innate sense of the divine.
  • A being that exists in reality is greater than a being that exists only in the mind. Anselm gives the example of a painter. The painting in his/her mind is greater once it has been painted because now it exists in reality as well as in the mind of the painter.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Weakness of version 1 of Anselm’s argument

A
  • Perhaps Anselm is confusing atheists with agnostics.
  • Is it possible to come up with a definition of God - a being of whom we have no knowledge nor empirical evidence?
  • Anselm doesn’t define what ‘greatness’ is - greatness means different things to different people.
  • He doesn’t tell us what God is - in himself - his nature. What is God like? Is God the God of Christian belief?
  • Gaunilo argues that the example of the painting is a poor analogy - there is a real difference between the initial idea and the finished product that we can see and experience!
  • Does the very definition of God prove his existence? Anselm is extremely vague in his reasoning.
  • My perfect May not be someone else’s perfect.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Who was Gaunilo?

A

Gaunilo was a Benedictine monk and contemporary of Anselm. Gaunilo believed in God. His argument was asking whether Anselm’s argument was philosophically sound, not questioning God’s existence. Gaunilo called his work ‘On behalf of the fool’ because he put himself in the position of a rational non-believer. The significance of Gaunilo being a monk is that he is a believer of God. He is arguing with someone who also believes in God. Usually theism versus atheist.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

What was Gaunilo’s criticism against version 1 of Anselm’s argument?

A

Gaunilo uses an example of a perfect island. If the perfect island did not exist, it would be a contradiction to call it the perfect island, for the perfect island would not be perfect if it did not exist. Therefore the perfect island, and anything else we think of as perfect must, by definition exist, it would be perfect.

To Gaunilo, this is absurd. The perfect island does not exist, just as perfect pens, books, tables and so on do not exist. Here, Gaunilo appeals to his own empiricist views. He asks his readers to look at the evidence of the world. There is no trace of these perfect beings - no perfect island, tables or books. He argues that if parallel arguments from perfection are absurd, then the original ontological argument is absurd.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

How did Anselm counter Gaunilo’s island criticism?

A

Anselm pointed out that an island is contingent. It’s very existence is contingent. That is, it depends on things like sea and earth. Islands do not have to exist, so their existence cannot be necessary. For there to be an island there must be other conditions fulfilled. This is true of any contingent being. There is nothing in the universe - as far as we can tell - that exists wholly independently of anything else. A table would not exist were there no materials or table-makers. Anselm argues that God is supremely necessary. He is not dependent on anything else, so the argument applies to him alone.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

What does John Hick say?

A

John Hick believes that the idea of the perfect island does not make sense because it is in definable. If I add one grain of sand or an extra palm tree to the perfect island, does it become imperfect or even more perfect? If we keep adding billions of grains of sand, it ceases to be a perfect island and becomes Australia, instead. Also, your perfect island is not my perfect island: I might hate coconuts.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

What does Anselm say about the fool?

A

Anselm believes that God cannot be thought not to exist. Some challenge this, saying that it would mean the ‘fool’ could not think that there is no God. How does Anselm address this challenge?

Anselm here directly addresses the issue. The verb he uses throughout the argument is intelligere, that is, ‘to understand’. It is not merely that the concept of God needs to be thought of. It needs to be really understood. Anselm says that the fool says what he does because he has not really understood the thought he had.

For example, I might tell you about an art exhibition I visited and say that there were amazing sculptures, some in eight dimensions, and an extraordinary picture of a nine-sided circle. If you were paying attention, you might point out that what I said was complete nonsense. The fact that I can use the swords dies nit mean either that ghetto make sense in themselves or that the way I use them entailed any understanding on my part. So it is with the fool. His sentence, ‘There is no God’, would be nonsense to any rational mind. The rational mind would think matters through. A weakness in Anselm’s response is that even fools do not, generally, deny what is truly self-evident.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

What is version 2 of Anselm’s ontological argument?

A

You cannot compare God to an island - an island is contingent - it relies on other things for its existence (sea, earth etc).

God is utterly different because God has necessary existence - meaning God must exist. God cannot not exist.

P1: It is possible to think of beings that come in and out of existence (contingent beings) and those that have necessary existence (must exist).

P2: A necessary being is greater than a contingent being.

P3: Since God is the greater conceivable being, God is a necessary being. Therefore, God cannot not exist.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

What are Aquinas’ criticisms of Anselm’s argument?

A

Aquinas believed that the ontological argument must be rejected:

  • It is possible to have a mental concept of the non-existence of God; people quite clearly manage it - including Anselm’s fool.
  • Anselm claims to know who ‘God’ is - but (like Gaunilo) Aquinas says that God is completely beyond our understanding. Any idea of God can only be in human terms, with all the limitations of human language and knowledge. God’s existence is hidden from us - including what it means to say that he exists.
  • We cannot know that our definition of God is correct so cannot use it as the basis for arguing for his existence.
  • The only way to God is indirectly - through examining the world around us.
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Strengths of Gaunilo’s criticisms

A
  • If an island is perfect, does an extra grain of sand or an extra palm tree ruin it?
  • Just because something exists in the mind, doesn’t mean it can exist in reality. For example, a unicorn.
  • The perfect something does not exist on this world like the perfect book or pen.
  • Does perfection even exist in this world?
  • Perfection is subjective. My perfect holiday might not be yours.
  • There is no trace of perfect beings.
  • It is possible to have a mental concept of the non-existence of God; people quite clearly manage it - including Anselm’s fool.
17
Q

Weakness of Gaunilo’s criticisms

A
  • The island is contingent whereas God is necessary. They are incomparable.
  • A necessary being is greater than a contingent being. Since God is the greater conceivable being, God is a necessary being. Therefore God cannot not exist.
18
Q

What is Descartes’ ontological argument?

A

Descartes starts with a definition of God…

  1. God is a supremely perfect being.
  2. A supremely perfect being contains supremely perfect characteristics (omni-benevolence, omnipotence…)
  3. Existence is an essential characteristic of a supremely perfect being.
  4. God’s existence is logically necessary. Therefore, God exists.

‘I cannot conceive God without existence’

For Descartes, existence cannot be separated from the essence of God. He uses two examples to illustrate his reasoning:

A triangle, to be a triangle, must have angles equivalent to 180 degrees. This is the essence of a triangle. Without the essence it is not a triangle. The idea of a mountain cannot be separated from the idea of a valley.

19
Q

Anselm or Descartes?

A

There are similarities in both arguments as well as differences. Anselm focused on the way in which God exists whereas Descartes looks more deeply into the quality of nature of God’s existence. Both arguments are important to consider.

Note: Descartes’ ontological argument is not in the specification so will not be named in an exam question. However, Kant’s criticisms of ontological argue,nuts are easier to understand if applied to Descartes’ version.

20
Q

What is Immanuel Kant’s first criticism of the ontological argument?

A

First, he considers two types of statements:

  • Synthetic statements: statements which require external (empirical) evidence to be proven true or false.
  • Analytical statements: statements which are true by definition - they contain the truth within the statement (a priori). Example: the word ‘bachelor’ contains the notion ‘single man’

Criticism: Statements about existence are synthetic, not analytic

To prove God’s existence, you need external, synthetic evidence. The ontological argument mistakenly gives a synthetic statement - ‘God exists’ - the status of an analytic statement.

Kant argues that it is logically necessary for a triangle to have three sides (Descartes’ example), but points out that this does not mean the triangle exists in reality. He is saying that just because we have an idea of God this does not mean that God actually exists. If God exists, then we can say that God is necessary (cannot not exist) - but if God does not exist then God does not exist necessarily!

21
Q

What is Kant’s second criticism of the ontological argument?

A

For his second criticism, Kant refers to the predicate of a sentence. In a sentence the predicate gives information about the subject (thing the sentence is about) - it expands our knowledge of the subject.

That’s a yellow chair
/\ /\
Predicate Subject

The predicate adds something to our understanding of the subject.

Existence is not a predicate. Kant argued that existence is not a real predicate (characteristic) of God because to say that God ‘exists’ adds nothing new to our understanding of God.

Kant asks us to imagine a pile of 100 coins. 100 real silver coins do not have any extra coins than 100 imaginary coins, says Kant. The existence of the coins adds nothing to the concept of the coins. He is showing that whether or not the concept of God is actualised (God is reality) cannot be resolved simply by adding existence’ to God’s different predicates.

Linking his two criticisms together, Kant points out that having 100 real silver coins could be verified synthetically and could make a real difference to a persons life.

22
Q

What did Bertrand Russell say about the ontological argument?

A

Although he was originally impressed by the ontological argument, Russell later rejected it, saying it makes a language error - It only appears right prove God’s existence. He asks us to think of the subject/predicate in the statement:

‘ The current King of France is bald’

Here, he smuggled in the assumption that there is a King of France. This is what Anselm and Descartes do - they smuggle in the assumption.

Furthermore, the use of predicates, like bald or not bald, is not enough to demonstrate that something exists. Existence must be established a posteriori - not assumed a priori.

23
Q

What did Richard Dawkins say about the Russell?

A

Richard Dawkins highlights the complex nature of the ontological argument, calling it a ‘riddle’ that is impossible for a non-believer to grasp - a ‘piece of trickery’. He says it is impossible to understand the terms ‘God’ or ‘necessary existence’.