Can one truly universalise actions without consideration of hypothetical outcomes Flashcards

(9 cards)

1
Q

INTRODUCTION
- Introduce Kantian ethics
- Explain that Kant sought universability
- What was the key method
- Whagt will the essay examine
- LOA

A

• Introduce Kantian ethics as a deontological theory developed in response to Enlightenment concerns about religious conflict and moral subjectivity.

• Explain that Kant sought a universal system of ethics grounded in pure reason, not contingent on religious belief or emotion.

• The key method of Kantian morality is the categorical imperative, which determines moral laws based on universalizability, not consequences.

• However, the essay will examine whether it is truly possible to universalise actions without regard to hypothetical outcomes, given real-life moral complexity.

Thesis/Line of argument: While Kant’s attempt to universalise morality independently of consequences has intellectual clarity and rigour, it fails in practice—true moral reasoning must consider hypothetical outcomes to be workable and humane.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

PARAGRAPH 1 – Kantian Deontology and the Categorical Imperative (AO1 + AO2)

AO1: The Basis of Kant’s Moral System

A

• Kant rejects morality based on subjective goals or hypothetical imperatives (e.g. “If you want to be liked, don’t lie”).

• Instead, he proposes categorical imperatives: unconditional moral commands that apply in all situations.

• The first formulation: act only according to maxims you can will as universal law.

• E.g., if everyone lied, trust would collapse, and lying would become impossible.

• Similarly, universalised stealing undermines property, so cannot be morally permissible.

• The second formulation: treat all people as ends, not mere means—respecting their autonomy.

• The third formulation: act as if you are a legislator in a kingdom of ends.

• Kant’s system demands moral actions be rational, universal, and independent of outcome.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

PARAGRAPH 1 – Kantian Deontology and the Categorical Imperative (AO1 + AO2)

A02

A

AO2: Strengths of Kant’s Theory

• By removing emotions and outcomes, Kant aims to avoid moral relativism and subjective inconsistency.

• His model reflects the Enlightenment ideal of moral objectivity and dignity for all rational agents.

• Kantian ethics thus offers an appealing moral clarity, immune to the corrupting influence of personal desires or situational pressures.

AO2: Critique – The Limits of Pure Universalisation

• Clashing Duties: Sartre’s example of the soldier torn between family duty and national duty shows that universal rules can conflict.

• Kant’s claim that imperfect duties can always be reconciled (e.g. finding someone else to care for a parent) fails when no such option exists.

• If “ought implies can,” then universalisation cannot tell us what to do when both duties are universalisable but not simultaneously possible.

• Therefore, Kant’s framework collapses in real-world moral dilemmas, undermining his goal to create a practical ethical guide.

• Emotion and Moral Motivation: Michael Stocker and Bernard Williams argue Kant neglects the ethical value of emotion-based motivation.

• A friend who visits out of duty, rather than care, lacks moral warmth; Williams calls this “one thought too many.”

• Kant’s rejection of emotions as morally valuable is implausibly cold and dehumanising.

• While Kant defends the stability of reason over the unreliability of emotions, Aristotle’s view—that reason can cultivate moral emotions (e.g. love, compassion)—is more psychologically accurate.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

PARAGRAPH 1 – Kantian Deontology and the Categorical Imperative (AO1 + AO2)

Conclusion

A

• Universalisation without regard to emotional or practical context often becomes rigid and morally alienating.

• Kant’s commitment to abstract reason undermines the human complexity of moral life.

• A workable ethics must acknowledge that even universal rules sometimes need interpretation in light of emotions and conflicting duties.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Paragraph 2

A

PARAGRAPH 2 – Consequences and the Limits of Ignoring Hypotheticals (AO1 + AO2)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

PARAGRAPH 2 – Consequences and the Limits of Ignoring Hypotheticals (AO1 + AO2)

AO1: Kant’s Rejection of Consequences

A

• Kant explicitly rejects consequentialist reasoning, arguing we can’t control outcomes and so shouldn’t base morality on them.

• The rightness of an action lies in its rational form, not in its result.

• His famous example: one must not lie, even to a murderer at the door seeking their victim.

• Lying would be morally wrong because it cannot be universalised, even if it might save a life.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

PARAGRAPH 2 – Consequences and the Limits of Ignoring Hypotheticals (AO1 + AO2)

AO2: Critique – Unrealistic and Morally Problematic

A

AO2: Critique – Unrealistic and Morally Problematic

• Benjamin Constant’s example reveals how this principle violates moral intuitions.

• If a Nazi asks whether we are hiding Jews, most people intuitively believe lying is the moral act.

• Kant’s response—that we could accidentally direct the murderer to their victim by lying—relies on a fallacious all-or-nothing view of control.

• Peter Singer’s concept of ‘reasonable expectation’ shows we can’t predict consequences perfectly, but we can judge them probabilistically and act accordingly.

• E.g., it is far more likely that lying will protect the hidden person, so it is ethically rational to lie.

• Ignoring consequences in such cases produces morally absurd outcomes, violating both common sense and compassion.

AO2: Evaluation – Consequences Cannot Be Ignored

• While Kant rightly points out the risks of calculating outcomes, this does not justify total rejection.

• We have a moral obligation to consider foreseeable outcomes, especially when lives are at stake.

• Moderate consequentialism does not require perfect prediction, just rational foresight.

• Kant’s moral absolutism fails to engage with moral risk, which is unavoidable in real ethical decisions.

• Ultimately, ethics must balance universal principles with situational awareness—pure universalisation is morally and practically insufficient.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Conclusion

A

• Kant’s vision of moral universalism was revolutionary, providing an impartial and rational basis for ethics.

• However, his exclusion of hypothetical outcomes, emotions, and situational nuance renders his system both incomplete and unworkable.

• Moral reasoning that refuses to account for practical consequences risks leading to inhumane results and logical contradictions.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

LOA

A

• Therefore, one cannot truly universalise moral actions without consideration of hypothetical outcomes.

• A robust ethical system must synthesise universal principles with practical reasoning and emotional intelligence to function in the real world.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly