Mens Rea Flashcards
(31 cards)
Function of mens rea
- To determine the intention (state of mind)
- Establish Blameworthiness
- Distinguishes between more or less cuplable state of mind
- Identifies the correct offence for which a D should be convicted
What does HLA Hart say about the mens rea
“The state society needs a moral license to punish”
Why might MR not just mean intent or act
Lack of defence + AR can satisfy it
Different states of mind/MR
- Intention
- Recklessness
- Knowledge/Belief
- Negligence
- Wilful
- SL
Quite generic but depends on the offence
Subjective MR
- Subjective fault is assessed by reference to D’s state of mind
- Requires D’s wrongful conduct to be reflected in state of mind
Intention + Recklessness
Objective MR
- Assessed by reference to the standards. Does not take into account what D actually thought but what he ought to have thought
- What we assume D thought
Negligence
Intention
- It is a person’s intention that counts in criminal law (not motive)
- For example, (Mercy Killing) Even though D’s motive is to alleviate V, of their suffering, the aim of D is still to kill, regardless of the ulterior motive
R v Adams [1957] - D (a doctor) doctrine of double effect.
R v Adams
Acting in a way that could cause victims death but also to alleviate pain and suffering
Point to the nicer intention
Direct intention
A person intends a result if he or she acts in order to bring it about
Moloney
Ordinary meaning
Duff test (not necessary in problem questions) like “but for”
A.K.A aim
Indirect Intention
Do not necessarily act to bring about the result
If D thought that the result was a virtually certain
Virtual Certainty
Although it was not D’s objective, the result was
- For all intents and purposes inevitable
- D knew this
R v Woollin “virtual certainty” as a result of D’s actions
Test for Indirect intention
1.) Type of intention requires consequence the virtual certainty of the D’s actions
2.) D appreciaetd/foresaw the consequeunces as a virtual certainty - Woolin allows some doubt here. If the act is virtually certain then the jury MAY find D intended the result. It is up to the jury to decided intention
Virtual Certainty - From Nedrick according to Thacker
Matthews and Alleyne
2.) D appreciaetd/foresaw the consequeunces as a virtual certainty - Woolin allows some doubt here. If the act is virtually certain then the jury MAY find D intended the result.** It is up to the jury to decided intention**
Why do people not like the elbow room in indirect intention and may finding D to intend that result as to whether there is VC
- Jury have too much autonomy to decide
Problem Cases within Intention
Indirect intention gives scope for motive - R v Adams. Due to elbow room for intention
Steane - D charged with assisting the enemy during WW2, if he did not they would hurt his family. Intention? Yes but no. Courts did not find Steane liable. **Motive here sometimes plays reasoning in this scenario, not to assist the enemy
**
BUT as compared to Re v Cox
- Administered a drug as well but no double effect here. Courts said medication did not have another purpose
- Re A - Manchester conjoined twins. If doctrine of double effect.
Intention does not necessarily help explain the moral gap - Stean
What happened in the case of Re A
In Re A (Conjoined Twins) [2000], the court had to decide whether it was lawful for doctors to separate conjoined twins, knowing that:
Jodie would survive if separated, but
Mary would certainly die.
The parents refused consent because they believed killing Mary was wrong.
The doctors sought a court declaration that separation would be lawful.
According to Ward LJ and Brooke LJ, the bad consequence (Mary’s death) wasn’t just a side-effect — it was inevitable and directly linked to the operation.
The operation was designed knowing it would kill Mary, because saving Jodie necessarily required Mary’s death.
Therefore, they couldn’t say: “We only intend the good (saving Jodie) and not the bad (killing Mary)”.
Double Effect
You are allowed to perform an act with a good intention even if you foresee a bad side effect, as long as the bad effect isn’t intended.
Summary of Intention for PQS
- In 99% of cases the jury should be asked simply ‘did A intend the consequence or not?’
- In 1% of cases, eg Woollin, they will need further guidance. They should be told that they can still find the consequence intended, although it was not the purpose of A’s action. If they think it was virtually certain to occur as a result of A’s action and A knew this. Foresight to a lesser degree of probability than certainty is not enough. This may be recklessness but not intention
- The jury are left with the final decision. They are entitled, not bound, to find a consequence intended if it was foreseen as certain.
Why do we need indirect intention
We need indirect intention - could easily be used as an excuse to say “oh I did not necessarily intend to kill”
- Think of the airplane case
Should intent only mean purpose?
Should intent only mean purpose?
Ideal concept of a voluntary act (Kessler Ferzan, 2002)
The result was endorsed by the defendant (Pedain, 1999)
“We are the authors of evil when we aim to achieve it in a way we are not if we merely anticipate that evil coming about as a result of our actions” (Moore, 1997, p.409)
But It opens up a dangerous set of arguments: “Not my purpose to kill, but to get X’s inheritance.”
But we cannot act and then pick and choose those consequences we wish to be responsible for:
“We cannot evade responsibility for any foreseen consequence of our acts by the plea that we felt no desire for them, either for their own sake or as means to ulterior ends…” (Sidgwick, 1907, p.202)
Is the ordinary meaning given to intent satisfactory?
Helpful intuitions (Pedain, 1999) or prejudices?
+ Plus confusion with virtual certainty and the scope of the jury
This also captures the evilness of choice instead of expanding it
It also only widens the scope of liability (indirect intention) and should we not be liable for our evil doings
Test for Recklessness
- D aware of risk that his conduct would cause a particular result (subjective)
- Risk unreasonable for D to take (2)
Element 1 of Recklessness
**R v Cunningham **- Subjective Foresight
(Did D foresee the risk?)
R v Parker - If one deliberately closes their eyes it still counts as foresight
Level of risk foreseen by D is irrelevant: Brady
D was aware of the risk that his conduct would cause harm
Recklessness: Objective Form Criticism
Widely criticised:
Sir John Smith: “This decisions sets back the law concerning the mental element in criminal damage in theory to before 1861.” (1981)
Issues around autonomy, choice, agency and voluntariness
The direction created problems for the young, mentally disabled, and inexperienced.
Elliot v C [1983] 2 All ER 1005