Behavioural Economics 5: Intertemporal Choice Flashcards

(35 cards)

1
Q

Define intertemporal choice and list factors that influence it.

A

Intertemporal choice = decisions involving trade-offs between costs and benefits at different times.
Influencing factors:
Anticipated changes in needs/preferences
Affordability now vs. later
Trust in future availability
Opportunity cost of waiting
Patience
Examples: saving vs. spending, studying now vs. later

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

What are the standard theories of intertemporal choice?

A

Historical foundations:
Arthur Pigou (1921): Future pleasures are seen “on a diminished scale.”
Adam Smith (1759): We are more interested in pleasures today than in 10 years.
William Stanley Jevons (1871): Concern diminishes as delay increases.
These early views emphasized psychological realism.
Later models focused on normative mathematical frameworks, often ignoring behavioural nuance.

look at picture

In normative theory, people should optimise where the marginal rate of substitution (MRS) equals the slope of the budget constraint.
Optimal condition:
−(1+r)=−(1+δ)⇒r=δ
Interpretation:
The interest rate (r) compensates for the discounting (δ) of future consumption.
In experiments:
People should prefer larger-later (LL) over smaller-sooner (SS) only if the experimental interest rate exceeds their personal discount rate.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Explain the exponential discounting model and its implications.

A
  • The first equation is ‘the present value of the outcome’
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

How do we calculate personal time preferences?

A

“t”’s units are in years

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

List and briefly describe experimental techniques used to measure time preferences.

A

Matching tasks: fill in the blank (e.g., £100 now = £X in 1 year)
Single binary choice: one SS vs. LL decision
Series of binary choices: multiple SS vs. LL decisions
Iterating tasks: staircase method to find indifference
Convex time budget: allocate tokens across time
Self-reports: rate willingness to delay gratification
Your note:
Works less well with goods that have diminishing marginal utility (e.g., snacks)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Describe ‘matching tasks’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Describe ‘single binary choice’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Describe ‘series of binary choices’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Describe ‘iterating time preference task’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A

Each question depends on the previous answer.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Describe ‘convex time budget task’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A

Participants allocate 100 tokens between two time periods.
Tokens for later periods are worth more (reflecting interest rate).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Describe ‘Self-Reported Patience’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Describe ‘Delayed Compensation Method (DCM)’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Describe ‘Marshmallow task’ as an experimental technique to elicit time preference

A
How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Describe the key difficulties and limitations in measuring time preferences through experiments.

A

⚠️ Challenges in Eliciting Time Preferences
Despite the variety of experimental methods, several practical and conceptual issues can affect the accuracy and reliability of elicited time preferences.

  1. Trust in Future Rewards
    Participants may not believe they will receive delayed payments.
    This lack of trust can artificially inflate discount rates.
    Especially problematic in lab settings with unfamiliar researchers.
  2. Transaction Costs
    Delayed rewards often require returning to the lab or waiting for a bank transfer.
    These inconveniences can bias participants toward smaller-sooner (SS) options.
    Easier to manage in online experiments.
  3. Difficulty with Non-Monetary Outcomes
    Most experiments use money, but real-world decisions often involve non-monetary goods (e.g., health, experiences).
    Problems:
    Can’t offer half a Ferrari now vs. a full one later.
    Many goods are not divisible or not linearly valued.
    Hard to calculate a discount rate for such goods.
    💸 Hypothetical vs. Real Rewards
    Does it matter if rewards are hypothetical?
    Kirby & Marakovic (1995):

Compared real vs. hypothetical matching tasks.
Found lower discount rates for hypothetical rewards.
Coller & Williams (1999):

Compared real vs. hypothetical choice tasks.
Found lower raw discount rates for hypothetical rewards.
But after regression controls, the difference disappeared.
Conclusion: Evidence is inconclusive. Some studies show differences, others do not.

❓ Are Elicited Discount Rates Meaningful?
Fuchs (1982):

Found no correlation between elicited time preferences and behaviours like smoking, credit card debt, or exercise.
Chapman & Coups (1999):

Found that employees who chose to get a flu shot had lower discount rates.
Munasinghe & Sicherman (2000):

Found that smokers had flatter wage profiles, suggesting less investment in human capital.
Addiction Studies:

Heroin addicts consistently show higher discount rates:
Alvos et al. (1993)
Kirby, Petry & Bickel (1999)
Madden et al. (1997)
Murphy & De Wolfe (1986)
Petry, Bickel & Arnett (1998)
Caveats:

Consider budget constraints.
Be aware of publication bias.
Overall: Mixed evidence on whether elicited discount rates predict real-world behaviour.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

What is domain specificity in intertemporal choice?

A

Domain specificity means that time preferences may vary across contexts.
Challenges the assumption that discounting is domain-general (i.e., stable across money, health, experiences, etc.).
Evidence suggests people may discount differently depending on the type of good or decision context.
Reference: Ubfal (2016)

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

What are the challenges in measuring time preferences for non-monetary goods?

A

To calculate a discount rate, the good must be:

Divisible – so you can vary the amount.
Linearly valued – utility should increase steadily with quantity.
Not quickly satiating – e.g., not like food or pleasure.
Without these, we can still study preference consistency and reversals, but not compute a precise discount rate.

17
Q

What methods have been used to study discounting beyond money?

A

🏥 Health:
Trade-offs between short illness now vs. longer illness later.
Social discounting: fatalities prevented now vs. later.
References: Van der Pol & Cairns; Cropper et al. (1992); Bleichrodt & Johannesson (2001)
🍫 Snacks:
Small snack now vs. bigger snack later.
Healthy now vs. unhealthy with future consequences.
Reference: Mischel et al. (1988); Read & van Leeuwen (1998)
🎬 Experiences:
Movies (high-brow vs. low-brow), electric shocks, kisses, noise, dinners, weekends, drugs.
Focus on preference reversals and sequence planning.
References: Loewenstein (1987); Read et al. (1999); Bickel et al. (2015)

18
Q

What is the significance of studying discounting beyond money?

A

Unlocks understanding of real-world behaviours (e.g., health, addiction, procrastination).
Helps design better policies and interventions.
Encourages development of new methods to measure time preferences in diverse domains.

19
Q

Explain the common difference effect and how it challenges standard discounting models.

A

People often prefer:
£110 in 31 days over £100 in 30 days (LL)
But prefer £100 today over £110 tomorrow (SS)
Standard theory predicts no change in preference since the time interval and reward difference are the same.
This preference reversal is called the common difference effect.
Reference: Green et al. (1994)

20
Q

Describe hyperbolic discounting and how it differs from exponential discounting.

A

In hyperbolic discounting, the discount rate declines over time.
People discount near-future rewards more steeply than far-future ones.
Example (Thaler, 1981):
£150 now vs. £X in 1 month → high discount rate
£150 now vs. £X in 1 year → lower discount rate
£150 now vs. £X in 10 years → even lower
Explains preference reversals and dynamic inconsistency.

21
Q

What is the sign effect in intertemporal choice?

A

People discount gains more than losses.
Example (Thaler, 1981):
£15 now = £X in 3 months (gain)
-£15 now = -£X in 3 months (loss)
People are more willing to delay losses than gains.
Suggests asymmetry in how we treat positive vs. negative outcomes.

22
Q

What is the magnitude effect in intertemporal choice?

A

Larger amounts are discounted less steeply than smaller ones.
Example (Thaler, 1981):
£15 now = £X in 1 year
£250 now = £X in 1 year
£3000 now = £X in 1 year
People are more patient with larger sums.

23
Q

What is the magnitude effect in intertemporal choice?

A

Larger amounts are discounted less steeply than smaller ones.
Example (Thaler, 1981):
£15 now = £X in 1 year
£250 now = £X in 1 year
£3000 now = £X in 1 year
People are more patient with larger sums.

24
Q

What is the delay/speedup asymmetry in intertemporal choice?

A

People react differently to delaying vs. speeding up outcomes.
Example (Loewenstein, 1988):
Delay: How much to accept to delay a £20 voucher by 8 weeks?
Speedup: How much to pay to get it 8 weeks earlier?
People demand more to delay than they’re willing to pay to speed up.
Shows framing matters.

25
What is the rate/amount asymmetry in intertemporal choice?
People are more patient when choices are framed as interest rates. Example (Read et al., 2005a): £400 today vs. £X in 6 months Framed as: “This is a 20% annual return” → more likely to wait Suggests numerical framing influences discounting.
26
What is the hidden zero effect in intertemporal choice?
People are more patient when foregone payoffs are made explicit. Example (Magen et al., 2008): Hidden: £100 today OR £150 in 1 year Explicit: £100 today and £0 in 1 year OR £0 today and £150 in 1 year Making the zero explicit increases awareness of opportunity cost.
27
List and briefly describe key anomalies in intertemporal choice.
Common difference effect: preference reversals when both options are delayed Hyperbolic discounting: discount rate declines over time Sign effect: losses discounted less than gains Magnitude effect: large amounts discounted less Delay/speedup asymmetry: framing matters Rate/amount asymmetry: interest rate framing increases patience Hidden zero effect: making opportunity cost explicit increases patience
28
What is dynamic inconsistency?
Preferences change over time → preference reversals Example: Prefer £110 in 1 year + 1 week over £100 in 1 year But prefer £100 now over £110 in 1 week Standard models can’t explain this Leads to suboptimal planning and regret
29
What is hyperbolic discounting?
Discount rate declines with delay Predicts: - Preference reversals - Dynamic inconsistency Loewenstein & Prelec (1992): generalized hyperbolic Intuition: we heavily discount near-term delays but not long-term ones
30
Explain the quasi-hyperbolic discounting model and its implications.
31
Use quasi-hyperbolic discounting to model procrastination.
32
What are Naifs and Sophisticates in intertemporal choice?
33
How do commitment devices help with time-inconsistent behaviour?
A commitment device imposes a cost for failing to follow through on a planned action. Helps Sophisticates align future behaviour with current intentions. Examples: Deposit money that is forfeited if goal isn’t met. Publicly announce goals. Use apps that block distractions. Key idea: Make the cost of procrastination outweigh the immediate disutility of action.
34
Give examples of real-world commitment device studies.
Giné, Karlan and Zinman (2009): CARES savings account for smoking cessation. 11% uptake; increased quit rates at 6 and 12 months. Houser et al. (2010): 36.4% used a device to block web surfing during tasks. Royer, Stehr and Sydnor (2011): Gym commitment contracts. 13% of full sample used them; 25% of gym members. Average stake: $63; max: $300.
35
How do commitment devices work in quasi-hyperbolic models?
Let: C = cost of action B = benefit X = penalty for not acting β < 1, δ = 1 Without commitment: Today: −C + βB < 0 → don’t act Tomorrow: 0 + β(−C + B) > 0 → plan to act → Procrastination With commitment (penalty X): Today: −C + βB > −X → act Tomorrow: 0 + β(−C + B) > −βX → still act → Commitment works if penalty is strong enough