Quick Summaries Flashcards

(53 cards)

1
Q

Ancient Philosophical Influences - Plato

A

Believes in two realms: the World of the Forms (perfect, eternal, unchanging) and the World of Appearances (imperfect, temporary, sensory).

The Form of the Good is the highest form, like the sun in his Allegory of the Cave, illuminating all knowledge.

Humans are born with innate knowledge of the Forms, and learning is recollection.

The soul is immortal and temporarily trapped in the body.

True knowledge (episteme) comes from rationalism (reason), not from the senses.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
2
Q

Ancient Philosophical Influences - Plato criticisms

A

Empiricism (e.g. Aristotle): knowledge comes from the senses, not innate ideas.

The Forms are too abstract – what is the Form of dirt or disease?

No evidence for a separate realm or immortal soul.

Popper: Plato’s ideal state leads to authoritarianism.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
3
Q

Ancient Philosophical Influences - Aristotle

A

Rejected Plato’s dualism and metaphysical Forms.

Believed the physical world is real and can be understood through empirical observation.

Developed the Four Causes to explain why things exist:
1. Material cause – what something is made from.
2. Formal cause – its structure or shape.
3. Efficient cause – what brings it into being.
4. Final cause (telos) – its purpose or end goal.

Believed everything has a purpose (teleology) and seeks to achieve its full potential.

The Prime Mover is an eternal, immaterial being that causes motion by attraction (not interaction), and is pure actuality.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
4
Q

Ancient Philosophical Influences - Aristotle criticisms

A

The Final cause is outdated in science (e.g. evolution has no purpose).

The Prime Mover doesn’t interact or care, unlike the God of classical theism.

Empirical method is powerful but not infallible – senses can be misleading.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
5
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Aristotle View

A

The soul is the form of a living body — it’s what makes a body alive.

Not a separate substance, but the “function” or essence of a thing.

The soul dies with the body; no afterlife.

Different types of soul: plant (growth), animal (sensation), human (reason).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
6
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Aristotle View Criticisms

A

Doesn’t account for near-death experiences or spiritual phenomena.

Lacks hope of an afterlife or immortality.

Some argue it reduces human beings to biological machines.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
7
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Descartes Dualism

A

Mind and body are two distinct substances: res cogitans (thinking thing) and res extensa (extended thing).

We know the mind exists because we can doubt everything except thought: “Cogito ergo sum”.

The body is physical and extended in space; the mind is non-physical and indivisible.

Interaction occurs in the pineal gland.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
8
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Descartes Dualism criticisms

A

Mind-body interaction is not clearly explained.

Neuroscience suggests mental states are linked to brain states.

Gilbert Ryle: calls dualism the “ghost in the machine”.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
9
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Plato Dualism

A

The soul is non-physical, immortal, and the source of reason and truth.

The body is temporary, physical, and distracts us from real knowledge.

At death, the soul returns to the world of the Forms.

The soul has three parts: reason (wisdom), spirit (courage), and appetite (desire), like the charioteer analogy in Phaedrus.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
10
Q

Soul, Mind and Body - Plato Dualism Criticisms

A

No evidence for the soul’s existence or reincarnation.

Ryle: this is a “category mistake”, treating the soul like a separate entity when it isn’t.

Doesn’t explain how mental states influence physical actions (mind-body interaction problem).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
11
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Ontological Argument (Anselm, Descartes)

A

A priori, analytic argument — based on logic and reason, not experience.

Anselm (Proslogion): God is “that than which nothing greater can be conceived.” If God only exists in the mind, a greater being could be imagined — one that exists in reality too. Therefore, God must exist in reality.

Descartes: God is a supremely perfect being; existence is a perfection; so God must exist by definition.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
12
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Ontological Argument (Anselm, Descartes) criticisms

A

Gaunilo’s island: using Anselm’s logic, you could “prove” anything perfect exists (e.g. perfect island), which is absurd.

Kant: existence is not a predicate — it doesn’t add anything to a concept.

Empiricists reject a priori arguments for existence — existence must be proven through experience.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
13
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Cosmological Argument (Aquinas, Kalam)

A

A posteriori — based on observation of cause and effect.

Aquinas’ 3 Ways (from Summa Theologica):

Motion — things are moved; must be a first unmoved mover (God).

Cause — there must be an uncaused first cause (God).

Contingency — everything contingent relies on something necessary (God).

Kalam version: Everything that begins to exist has a cause. The universe began to exist. Therefore, the universe has a cause (God).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
14
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Cosmological Argument (Aquinas, Kalam)

A

Hume: we cannot infer a necessary being from contingent ones.

Russell: universe may just be a “brute fact” — no explanation needed.

Fallacy of composition: just because all parts have causes doesn’t mean the whole does.

Quantum physics challenges causality at a subatomic level.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
15
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Teleological Argument (Design)

A

A posteriori, inductive — based on apparent design and order in nature.

Aquinas’ Fifth Way: non-rational objects act towards an end; must be directed by something intelligent (God).

Paley’s Watchmaker: a watch implies a designer; the natural world (e.g. eye, solar system) also implies design.

Tennant’s Anthropic Principle: the universe seems “fine-tuned” to support human life — this is best explained by a designer.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
16
Q

Argument for the Existence of God - Teleological Argument (Design) criticisms

A

Hume: analogy is weak — universe is not like a watch; could be made by many gods, or trial and error.

Darwin & Evolution: apparent design can be explained by natural selection.

Problem of evil: if God designed the world, why so much suffering and flawed design?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
17
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - The Problem of Evil: Logical Problem (Epicurus, Mackie)

A

Claims the existence of evil is logically incompatible with an all-powerful, all-loving God.

Epicurus’ Inconsistent Triad: If God is willing to prevent evil but not able, He is not omnipotent; if able but not willing, He is not omnibenevolent; if both, why is there evil?

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
18
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - The Problem of Evil: Evidential Problem (Rowe, Dostoevsky)

A

Argues the extent and type of suffering (e.g. natural disasters, child torture) make it improbable that an all-good, all-powerful God exists.

Rowe: some suffering appears pointless (e.g. fawn in a forest fire).

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
19
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - The Problem of Evil: Criticisms (Theodicies)

A

Augustine: Evil is the privation of good; God made everything good, but humans misused free will. Evil and suffering are the result of original sin.

Irenaeus/Hick: Soul-making theodicy — suffering helps develop moral and spiritual maturity. Earth is a place of soul development.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
20
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - The Problem of Evil: Criticisms of Theodicies

A

Augustine’s view implies a perfect world went wrong, which seems logically flawed.

Why would a perfect being create fallible beings? And why eternal punishment for inherited sin?

Hick’s soul-making is criticised as justifying extreme suffering — e.g. genocide — for the sake of growth.

Doesn’t account for animal suffering or natural evil that seems unrelated to human development.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
21
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - Religious Belief as a Product of the Human Mind (Freud)

A

Religion is a psychological illusion, stemming from the unconscious mind’s need for security and a father figure.

Rooted in Oedipus complex: repressed desires and guilt are transferred onto an imagined divine figure.

Religion is a form of wish fulfilment — an escape from reality and a way to cope with death and suffering.

How well did you know this?
1
Not at all
2
3
4
5
Perfectly
22
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - Religious Belief as a Product of the Human Mind (Freud) criticisms

A

Jung: religion is a positive part of the collective unconscious; it helps achieve psychological integration.

Freud’s view is reductionist — it ignores the philosophical and spiritual dimensions of faith.

Assumes atheism is rational and religion is neurotic, which may be biased.

23
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - Religious Belief as a Product of the Human Mind (Marx)

A

Religion is the “opium of the people” — used by the ruling class to oppress the working class.

It legitimises suffering (e.g. promising heaven) and discourages rebellion.

A tool for social control — encourages obedience and false consciousness.

24
Q

Challenges to Religious Belief - Religious Belief as a Product of the Human Mind (Marx) criticisms

A

Too economically deterministic — ignores personal spiritual experiences.

Religion has also been a force for social change (e.g. liberation theology, civil rights movement).

Not all religion supports the status quo.

25
Religious Language - The Verification Principle
(Associated with Logical Positivism, especially A.J. Ayer) A statement is only meaningful if it is analytically true (true by definition) or synthetically verifiable (provable by sense experience). Religious statements (e.g. “God exists”) are neither analytic nor empirically verifiable, so they are considered meaningless. Example: “God loves us” cannot be verified through experience or logic.
26
Religious Language - The Verification Principle criticisms
Fails its own test: the principle itself cannot be empirically verified — it’s self-defeating. Too narrow — it would rule out ethical, historical, and scientific theories that can’t be verified directly. Swinburne: statements like “all ravens are black” are meaningful even if not verifiable now.
27
Religious Language - The Falsification Principle
(Developed by Karl Popper; applied to religion by Antony Flew) For a statement to be meaningful, there must be a possible scenario that could prove it false. Flew argued religious believers refuse to let go of their beliefs, no matter what — making them unfalsifiable and thus meaningless. Used the parable of the invisible gardener: both believers and non-believers see the same evidence but draw different conclusions.
28
Religious Language - The Falsification Principle Responses
R.M. Hare: introduced the idea of "bliks" — non-falsifiable but deeply meaningful worldviews (e.g. paranoid man who thinks all dons want to kill him). Basil Mitchell: religious faith can allow trust in God despite evidence (parable of the partisan and the stranger).
29
Religious Language - The Falsification Principle criticisms
Bliks are too subjective — if anything can be a blik, we lose all standards of rationality. Mitchell’s view is seen as a cop-out by critics — faith might persist in face of contrary evidence, but it’s unclear how this is rational.
30
Religious Language - Analogical and Symbolic Language (Aquinas and Tillich)
Aquinas’ Analogy of Proportion and Attribution We can speak meaningfully about God through analogy (not univocally or equivocally). Attribution: we learn about God by seeing the effects (e.g. goodness in creation). Proportion: we understand God’s attributes in relation to ours, but in a higher, infinite form. Paul Tillich — Symbolism Religious language is symbolic, not literal. Symbols participate in the reality they represent (e.g. cross symbolizes salvation). Symbols open levels of reality and deepen understanding, like art or music.
31
Religious Language - Analogical and Symbolic Language (Aquinas and Tillich) criticisms
Analogical language may still not clarify what God is actually like. Symbolism depends on culture — symbols can change or die out (e.g. swastika). Some argue symbolic language is too vague for theological use.
32
Religious Language - Language as Non-Cognitive: Via Negativa (Apophatic Way)
Via Negativa (Apophatic Way) We cannot speak of what God is, only what He is not (e.g. God is not evil, not finite). Prevents reducing God to human terms.
33
Religious Language - Language as Non-Cognitive: Via Negativa (Apophatic Way) criticisms
Doesn’t help us build a positive understanding of God. Could make God too remote or impersonal. Still uses language — saying "God is not X" assumes we know what X is.
34
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omnipotence (all-powerful)
Aquinas: God can do anything logically possible (can’t make square circles). Descartes: God can do anything at all, even logically impossible things — true omnipotence. Vardy & Macquarrie: God’s power is self-limited so that humans have free will. Geach: ‘Almighty’ ≠ ‘can do anything’, but rather supreme power over everything.
35
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omnipotence (all-powerful) criticisms
Logical paradoxes: Can God create a stone He cannot lift? If God can do anything, He could do evil — contradicts omnibenevolence. Limiting God’s power (e.g. for free will) raises the question: is He really omnipotent?
36
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omniscience (all-knowing)
God knows everything — past, present, and future. But if God knows the future, do we have free will? (compatibilism vs determinism) Some say God’s knowledge is timeless — He knows all things eternally. Others say God is everlasting in time — He knows all that can be known at each moment.
37
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omniscience (all-knowing) criticisms
If God knows what we’ll do, we’re not free — moral responsibility disappears. If we’re free, God can’t know future choices = limits His omniscience.
38
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omnibenevolence (all-good)
God is supremely loving and morally perfect. Often supported through scripture (e.g. “God is love” in 1 John). Justifies creation, grace, and moral law.
39
The Nature or Attributes of God - Omnibenevolence (all-good) criticisms
Problem of evil: too much suffering to reconcile with an all-loving God. Hell contradicts benevolence — why eternal punishment?
40
The Nature or Attributes of God - God and Eternity: Timeless (Atemporal)
1. Timeless (Atemporal) — God is outside of time Aquinas and Boethius: God sees all of time at once (like from above a timeline). God doesn’t change; He is immutable and eternal. Boethius: God’s knowledge doesn’t cause our actions, so we remain free.
41
The Nature or Attributes of God - God and Eternity: Timeless (Atemporal) criticisms
God can’t respond or act in time (e.g. answer prayers). Makes God seem impersonal.
42
The Nature or Attributes of God - God and Eternity: Everlasting (Sempiternal)
2. Everlasting (Sempiternal) — God exists within time Swinburne: God exists through time but has no beginning or end. Allows for interaction and real relationships with humans.
43
The Nature or Attributes of God - God and Eternity: Everlasting (Sempiternal) criticisms
May limit God's perfection and changelessness. Suggests He’s subject to time, like us.
44
Religious Language After the 20th Century - Wittgenstein (Language Games)
Meaning is use — language gets its meaning from its context and community. Religious language is part of a “language game” — meaningful to those who participate (e.g. believers). Don’t judge religious statements by scientific or empirical standards — they’re not in the same game.
45
Religious Language After the 20th Century - Wittgenstein (Language Games) strengths
Explains why religion is meaningful to believers even if not empirically verifiable. Avoids forcing religion into scientific frameworks.
46
Religious Language After the 20th Century - Wittgenstein (Language Games) criticisms
Risks making religion relativistic — if meaning is just internal, no criticism is possible. Outsiders may say it protects religion from rational debate.
47
Religious Language After the 20th Century - Hick's Eschatological Verification
Religious statements are verifiable in principle — at the end of time (eschaton), their truth will be known. Like two men walking down a road, one believing it leads to a celestial city, the other not — they’ll find out at the end. Therefore, claims like “God exists” are not meaningless, even if they can’t be verified now.
48
Religious Language After the 20th Century - Hick's Eschatological Verification criticisms
Depends on life after death being real — if it isn’t, the claim remains unverifiable. Still not empirically testable in this life.
49
Religious Experience - What is Religious Experience
Personal experiences where individuals claim to have encountered God, the divine, or the sacred. Can be mystical (union with God), conversion experiences, or numinous (awe-inspiring, beyond normal experience). Used as an argument for the existence of God or at least evidence of something beyond the physical.
50
Religious Experience - Types of Religious Experience
William James’ Four Characteristics: 1. Ineffability — beyond words. 2. Noetic Quality — imparts knowledge. 3. Transiency — temporary. 4. Passivity — feeling controlled by an outside force. Numinous Experience (Rudolf Otto): Encounter with the ‘Wholly Other’ — awe and mystery. Mixed feelings of fascination and fear (“mysterium tremendum et fascinans”).
51
Religious Experience - Religious Experience as Evidence for God
Swinburne’s Principle of Credulity: We should believe experiences unless there is strong reason not to. Principle of Testimony: > People generally tell the truth about their experiences. Religious experiences provide direct evidence of God’s existence for the experiencer.
52
Religious Experience - Criticisms of Religious Experience
Subjectivity: Experiences are private and personal, difficult to verify. Psychological explanations: Freud: Religious experiences as illusions or neuroses. Hood’s ‘God Helmet’ experiments show brain stimulation can induce mystical feelings. Cultural Conditioning: Experiences often shaped by expectations and cultural background. Conflicting Experiences: Different religions claim contradictory experiences, undermining universal truth. Logical Issues: Even if experiences are genuine, they don’t prove which religion (if any) is true.
53
Religious Experience - Responses
Swinburne accepts that no experience is infallible, but collective evidence from multiple experiences strengthens the case. Alston argues for a “properly basic belief” in God grounded in experience, akin to trusting our senses.